Skip to main content

Separation of Body and Soul in Plato’s Phaedo: An Unprecedented Ontological Operation in the Affinity Argument

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 139))

Abstract

The paper aims to address the problem of the separation of body and soul in Plato’s Phaedo, in search of both its ontological features and moral consequences. Apart from the normal approach and use of dialogue as a literary and philosophical milestone for all body-soul dualisms in the history of philosophy, I believe two different ways of understanding this separation are outlined in the dialogue. The first one would indicate a moral separation, regarding what a philosopher should take care of: philosophers are supposed to mind the soul and not the body. A different way to address this separation between body and soul is the one I would like to consider as an ontological separation: the soul is so independent from the body that is declared to survive after its death. In a way, the dualistic ontology of individuals forcefully follows the bodily engagement of a chameleon-like soul in its wandering, both epistemological and moral, through the sensible world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the standard version of the body-mind problem in the Phaedo, see Fierro (2013).

  2. 2.

    Broadie (2001, p. 307) and Carone (2005, p. 245) rightly stressed the relevance of this ethical dualism in the Phaedo. Woolf (2004) proposes a further and very sharp distinction between a weaker, called evaluative dualism, and a stronger ascetic reading of the separation. For Pitteloud (2017, pp. 58–82), the separation between soul and body must be understood in the light of the separation between Forms and sensible objects. See also Pakaluk (2003) on the maximization of the death as core concern of a philosophical life: the philosopher aims to be as dead as possible while alive; hence, he welcomes the maximal condition of death, when it arrives (2003, p. 99).

  3. 3.

    See Ostenfeld (1987), Frede (1999), Broadie (2001), Carone (2005), Fronterotta (2007), and Fierro (2013) for a wider account of the debate.

  4. 4.

    At the same time I distance myself from Carone (2005). She claims that Plato, in his later dialogues, would have left behind the strong dualistic commitments of the Phaedo by allowing that the mind may be the subject of spatial movements. I believe some kind of indecision and nuances on his dualistic approach can be seen right from the Phaedo itself, i.e. from at least the middle dialogues. See also Johannsen (2000) claiming that in the Timaeus, Plato is ascribing spatial properties to soul and body alike.

  5. 5.

    Here it is important to note that the word εἶδος doesn’t have, in the passage under discussion, the technical meaning of idea/form. This connotation of the word is going to play an important role later on in the dialogue (see Phd 103e).

  6. 6.

    Fierro (2013, p. 21) rightly points out that the comparative ὁμοιότερον here (along with the superlative ὁμοιότατον @80b) reveals that the ontological difference between the soul and the body is more attenuated than the one between the intelligible and the sensible realms. Casertano (2015 @79b) follows a similar line of thought: “this comparative leads, logically to (1) that the soul is not the invisible, but it is more invisible than the body; (2) that the body is also similar to the invisible, but less invisibile than the soul”.

  7. 7.

    Apolloni (1996, p. 7) is rightly trying to recover the argument’s value, by taking it as a deductive proof and a philosophically more worthy of attention piece than, for example, the arguments of the reminiscence or the final argument.

  8. 8.

    Boetus’ criticism and text have been regrettably omitted by Eusebius. For a discussion of this omission, see Gertz (2011, pp. 126–29).

  9. 9.

    Another image, quite expressive, of the inevitability of this somatization is the one of the souls wandering as ghosts by the tombs (Phd 81d). See Gertz (2011, p. 29) on the reading of this very passage by Ammonium.

  10. 10.

    Both the ideas of the palingenesis, which is a core point in the first argument for the immortality in the Phaedo (70c-72e), and the anamnesis, the second argument (72e-77a), also imply a kind of inclination of the soul towards the coupling with the body (in the first argument) and a positive function of the senses since knowledge is the result from an interaction between the information that our senses give us and universal notions, under which we classify our sense data (see Fierro, 2013, p. 24, and Scott, 1987, p. 348).

  11. 11.

    Pakaluk (2003, p. 99) inspired this conclusion in his inquiring to what extent does a true philosopher achieves a philosophical life by practicing death in living. Our conclusions here are quite different, of course, since he’s not willing to admit some kind of influence of the epistemological and ethical effort of the philosopher on the ontological endurance of the dualism. This latter idea has been discussed in a recent talk with Thomas Johannsen at Brasenose College, Oxford. I’m deeply grateful for his insights, and I should admit that this paper owns a large debt to him.

References

  • Apolloni, D. (1996). Plato’s affinity argument for the immortality of the soul. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 34(1), 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bostock, D. (1986). Plato’s Phaedo. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, S. (2001). Soul and body in Plato and descartes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101(2), 295–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casertano, G. (2015). Platone. Il Fedone. Dramma etico in tre atti. Napoli, Italy: Paolo Loffredo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carone, G. R. (2005) Mind and body. In Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, Volume 87 issue 3 https://doi.org/10.1515%2Fagph.2005.87.3.227

  • Dorter, K. (1976). The Phaedo’s final argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6(Sup1), 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixsaut, M. (1985). Le naturel philosophe: Essai sur les dialogues de Platon (Collection d’études anciennes). Paris: Les Belles lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, M. (1997). The role of the affinity argument in the Phaedo. Phronesis, 42(3), 313–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frede, D. (1978). The final proof of the immortality of the soul in Plato’s Phaedo 102a – 107a. Phronesis, 23(1), 27–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frede, D. (1999). Platons “Phaidon”: Der Traum von der Unsterblichkeit der Seele(Werkinterpretationen). Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fronterotta, F. (2007). Carone on the mind-body problem in late Plato. Archiv Für Geschichte Der Philosophie, 89(2), 231–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fierro, M. A. (2013). Alma encarnada-cuerpo amante en el Fedón de Platón. In L. Benítez Gorbet & A. Velázquez Zaragoza (Eds.), Tras las huellas de Platón y el platonismo en la filosofía moderna. De su simiente griega a la ilustración (pp. 7–42). México, DF: Editorial Torres Asociados.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gertz, S. R. P. (2011). Death and immortality in late neoplatonism: Studies on the ancient commentaries on Plato’s Phaedo. Leiden, Netherlands: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, T. (2000). Body, soul and tripartion in Plato’s Timaeus. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, XIX, 87–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostenfeld, E. (1987). Ancient Greek psychology: And the modern mind-body debate. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pakaluk, M. (2003). Degrees of separation in the Phaedo. Phronesis, 48(2), 89–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitteloud, L. (2017). La séparation dans la métaphysique de Platon. Sankt Augustin, Germany: Plato International Studies, Academia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, C. (1993). Plato. Phaedo. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D. (1987). Platonic Anamnesis Revisited. Classical Quaterly 37(2):346–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trabattoni, F. (2011). Platone. Fedone. Milano, Italy: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolf, R. (2004). The Practice of a Philosopher. In Oxford studies in ancient philosophy (Vol. XXVI, pp. 100–120). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabriele Cornelli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cornelli, G. (2019). Separation of Body and Soul in Plato’s Phaedo: An Unprecedented Ontological Operation in the Affinity Argument. In: Pitteloud, L., Keeling, E. (eds) Psychology and Ontology in Plato. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 139. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04654-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics