Skip to main content

Social Facts and Law: Why the Rule of Recognition is a Convention

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 126))

Abstract

The author shows that the existence of law in a given society requires the presence of a unitary practice of identification of rules (a rule of recognition). It is also argued that the best way of understanding this rule is to see it as a constitutive convention, which allows the autonomous identification of the law of a particular community. According to this author, just as the existence of money requires the belief that it exists, the existence of a legal system depends ultimately on a set of beliefs shared by the relevant persons. After developing this position, a series of recurrent criticisms of conventionalist positions is reviewed with the aim of rejecting them. These criticisms are: if the rule of recognition is understood as a convention then it cannot account for the normative nature of the convention, nor for the presence of principles in legal systems, nor for the disagreements between lawyers; finally, the problem of the arbitrariness of the rule of recognition and its alleged banality is addressed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The formulation of these counterfactuals is taken from Narváez (2004), p. 280.

  2. 2.

    Lewis (1969).

  3. 3.

    See Lagerspetz (1995); Marmor (1996), pp. 349–371; Shapiro (2001), pp. 149–191; Coleman (1998), pp. 381–425; Coleman (2001); Bayón (2002), pp. 33–54; Narváez (2004); Vilajosana (2003), pp. 41–63; Vilajosana (2006), pp. 521–538; Vilajosana (2010a).

  4. 4.

    Hart (1961), p. 147.

  5. 5.

    See Hart (1994), p. 256.

  6. 6.

    See Hart (1961), p. 134.

  7. 7.

    The latter is an application of the characterisation of the Lewis convention (1969). His different definition of “convention”, which is even more sophisticated, can be found on p. 42, p. 56, and p. 78.

  8. 8.

    See Kelsen (1960), p. 202.

  9. 9.

    Hart (1961), p. 132.

  10. 10.

    See Searle (1995).

  11. 11.

    Prieto Sanchís (2008), p. 491 (free translation by the author). See my response in Vilajosana (2008), pp. 507–536.

  12. 12.

    Nino (1982), p. 60.

  13. 13.

    On this criticism, see Ruiz Manero (1990), pp. 130–132.

  14. 14.

    For example, following the line argued by Lagerspetz (1995), p. 159 ff.

  15. 15.

    As expressed by Coleman (2001), p. 101. See also, in similar terms, Shapiro (2001), pp. 149–191. I fear, however, that Shapiro would no longer agree with what I affirm in the text, taking into account what he maintains in Shapiro (2011).

  16. 16.

    About the role of efficacy, see Vilajosana (2010b), pp. 103–118.

  17. 17.

    In the sense expressed by Andrei Marmor, who I follow on this point. See Marmor (2001a), p. 200.

  18. 18.

    One of the first to attempt this was Postema (1982), pp. 165–203.

  19. 19.

    In the same sense, see Coleman (2001), p. 95. It should be noted that this author has changed his position on this point, given that in previous work he had aligned himself, together with Postema, with the more mimetic translation of the framework of Lewis in the problem that concerns us.

  20. 20.

    See Marmor (1996), pp. 349–371.

  21. 21.

    Vilajosana (2003), pp. 41–63. It seems that, in posterior writings, Marmor did also realise that this compatibility is possible. For the proposal of Marmor, see Tusset (2007), pp. 179–198.

  22. 22.

    Hart himself gave cause for it by considering that the rule of recognition, despite being a secondary rule, imposes obligations. See, in this respect, the controversy that Ruiz Manero and Bulygin have maintained in the journal Doxa: Bulygin (1991), pp. 311–318; Ruiz Manero (1991), pp. 281–293.

  23. 23.

    Recall the counterfactual that lies behind every convention I mention at the beginning of this work.

  24. 24.

    This is what, for example, MacCormicck and Weinberg (1986), pp. 132–133; Garzón (1993), pp. 317–335, do.

  25. 25.

    For criticisms on the attempts to establish the binding character of conventions, see Green (1988), pp. 117–121; Celano (1995), pp. 15–77; Marmor (2001b), pp. 28–29.

  26. 26.

    See Lewis (1969). If this element were not present, the problem of coordination at the source of each convention would not be resolved.

  27. 27.

    See Vilajosana (2007), chapter IV.

  28. 28.

    For the criticism outlined in this section and in the following section, see Dworkin (1977, 1986).

  29. 29.

    Dworkin (1986), p. 225.

  30. 30.

    Anscombe (1957), p. 84 ff. In the same sense, see Celano (1995), p. 54.

  31. 31.

    Celano (2003), p. 351 (free translation from Italian). In similar terms, see Shapiro (2011).

  32. 32.

    For the concept of arbitrariness, see Marmor (2006), pp. 683–704.

  33. 33.

    See Lewis (1969), pp. 76–80.

  34. 34.

    For the identity of legal orders and precisely the relation with these questions of value, I refer to Vilajosana (1997).

  35. 35.

    Celano (2003), p. 353.

  36. 36.

    If we interpret, a sensu contrario, what is said in Celano (2003), p. 347.

  37. 37.

    Celano has himself admitted a non-vicious circularity in relation with his vision of customary norms as social rules. See Celano (1995), pp. 15–77.

References

  • Anscombe GEM (1957) Intention. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayón JC (2002) El contenido mínimo del positivismo jurídico. In: Zapatero V (coord) Horizontes de la filosofía del derecho: homenaje a Luís García San Miguel, vol 2. pp 33–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin E (1991) Regla de reconocimiento: ¿Norma de obligación o criterio conceptual? Réplica a Juan Ruiz Manero. Doxa 9:311–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celano B (1995) Consuetudini, convenzioni. In: Comanducci P, Guastini R (eds) Analisi e diritto. Giappichelli, Torino, pp 15–77. Spanish translation by Moreso J J, cited as: Costumbres, convenciones. In: Dos estudios sobre la costumbre. Fontamara, México 2000

    Google Scholar 

  • Celano (2003) La regola di riconoscimento è una convenzione? Ragion Pratica 21:347–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JL (1998) Incorporationism, conventionality, and the practical difference thesis. Leg Theory 4:381–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JL (2001) The practice of principle: in defence of a pragmatism approach to legal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Garzón E (1993) Algo más acerca de la relación entre el derecho y la moral. In: Derecho, Ética y Política. C.E.C, Madrid, pp 317–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Green L (1988) The authority of the State. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1961) The concept of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1994) In: Bulloch P, Raz J (eds) Postscript to the concept of law, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1960) Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd edn. Frans Deuticke, Wien

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerspetz E (1995) The opposite mirrors. An essay on the conventionalist theory of institutions. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Convention. A philosophical study. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormicck N, Weinberg O (1986) An institutional theory of law. New approches to legal positivism. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (1996) On convention. Synthese 107:349–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2001a) Legal conventionalism. In: Coleman J (ed) Hart’s postcript. Essays on the postscript to the concept of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 193–217

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2001b) Positive law and objective values. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2006) Legal positivism: still descriptive and morally neutral. Oxf J Leg Stud 26(4):683–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narváez M (2004) Wittgenstein y la teoría del derecho. Una senda para el convencionalismo jurídico. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino CS (1982) Introducción al análisis del derecho. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Postema GJ (1982) Coordination and convention at the foundations of law. J Leg Stud 11:165–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prieto Sanchís L (2008) Identificación y justificación del derecho. Anuario de Filosofía del derecho 25:487–506

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz Manero J (1990) Jurisdicción y normas. C.E.C, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz Manero J (1991) Normas independientes, criterios conceptuales y trucos verbales; Respuesta a Eugenio Bulygin. Doxa 9:281–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. Simon and Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro SJ (2001) On Hart’s way out. In: Coleman J (ed) Hart’s postcript. Essays on the postscript to the concept of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 149–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro SJ (2011) Legality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tusset G (2007) The social reality of law. In: Comanducci P, Guastini R (eds) Analisi e diritto. Giappichelli, Torino, pp 179–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Ullmann-Margalit E (1977) The emergence of norms. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (1997) El significado político del derecho. Fontamara, México

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2003) Hechos sociales y Derecho. In: Diciotti E, Velluzzi V (eds) Ordinamento giuridico, sovranità, diritti. Giappichelli, Torino, pp 41–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2006) El positivismo jurídico convencionalista. In: Ramos Pascua JA, Rodilla MA (eds) El positivismo jurídico a examen. Estudios en homenaje a José Delgado Pinto. Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca, Salamanca, pp 521–538

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2007) Identificación y justificación del derecho. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2008) A las puertas del paraíso. Respuesta a Luís Prieto Sanchís. Anuario de Filosofía del derecho 25:507–536

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2010a) El derecho en acción. La dimensión social de las normas jurídicas. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilajosana JM (2010b) Eficacia normativa y existencia del derecho. Teoría & derecho. Revista de pensamiento jurídico 8:103–118

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Josep M. Vilajosana .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Vilajosana, J.M. (2019). Social Facts and Law: Why the Rule of Recognition is a Convention. In: Ramírez-Ludeña, L., Vilajosana, J. (eds) Legal Conventionalism. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 126. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03571-6_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03571-6_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-03570-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-03571-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics