Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 20))

  • 500 Accesses

Abstract

For more than 50 years now, Donnellan’s distinction between referential and attributive descriptions has been discussed, criticized, supported and considered from many points of view. The facts have largely been agreed upon but the debate still revolves around how to account for them, especially for referring by a misdescription, i.e., a description that does not fit what it is being used to refer to, for example when I refer to the man near the window as the man drinking a martini, whereas he has a tonic water. Here, I offer a reconstruction of the issue and sketch a meaning as use framework (in fact, Donnellan distinguishes two uses of descriptions), within which I discuss an account for referential descriptions, including apparent ones. Before closing, I put forward a unitary account of the two uses of a description, whereby the descriptive condition is always relevant, while denying that a description in referential use operates in the same way as a proper name.

I dedicate this piece to Joseph Almog, who taught me this topic and much more besides. I have been thinking about the Donnellan case for a long time, presenting on many occasions ancestors of the present paper. I am grateful to Roberta Ballarin, Andrea Bianchi, Claudia Bianchi, Pierdaniele Giaretta, Petr Kot’acko, Diego Marconi, Ernesto Napoli, Carlo Penco, John Perry, Marco Santambrogio, and Tim Williamson for criticisms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Russell 1905 and Strawson 1950.

  2. 2.

    Among the critics to this paper are Castañeda 1977 and Neale 1990 (although Neale partially revised his position in Neale 2004; see also Ludlow and Neale 2006). Among the most favorable is Davidson 1986. See Evans 1982 for a more elusive stance. For a pro-Donnellan set of papers, see Almog and Leonardi 2012 (of particular interest is Kaplan 2012).

  3. 3.

    This quote is part of a passage discussing Donnellan’s use of referential. Contrasting reference and denotation, one could offer a general account of referential descriptions (i.e., descriptions and misdescriptions) as pragmatic. For a semantic contrast between reference and denotation, see Capuano 2012. Later, we shall see that not all apparent misdescriptions are one.

  4. 4.

    See also Reimer 1998.

  5. 5.

    Devitt, as Howie Wettstein, claims that we refer using descriptions, but denies that a misdescription refer – meaning, I take, that referring by a misdescription is not a semantic phenomenon.

  6. 6.

    As Searle, Kiefer, and Bierwisch write: “in a meaning as use framework there is no clear separation between semantics and pragmatics, and generally the term ‘pragmatics’ does not even occur” (1980: x–xi).

  7. 7.

    See Martí (2008) and Recanati 2013.

  8. 8.

    The literature on Donnellan referential/attributive distinction is large, consisting in several hundred essays. Amongst many of whom I shall skip, Almog (2012, 2014), and Capuano 2012 take the most extreme stance, insofar as they deny that definite descriptions ever denote – they only refer. Bezuidenhout 2013, meanwhile, complains about how much the philosophical debate on descriptions is detached from the empirical considerations concerning linguists. She surmised a unitary view of definite descriptions, distinguishing those that are attributive from those that are referential as having different focuses – the first on role properties, the second on role bearers (cf. 358ff). Her solution is suprasegmental. Penco 2017 applies the idea of loose talk (see also Sperber and Wilson 1986). However, this sophisticated solution deprives Donnellan’s distinction of its semantic import.

  9. 9.

    See Almog (2012, 2014).

  10. 10.

    Published as Kripke 2013.

  11. 11.

    One page later, he added:

    Hence, as a theory of definite descriptions, Russell’s view seems to apply, if at all, to the attributive use only (1966: 293 – my italics).

    In the 1977 paper, Kripke quoted this remark. He read it as somehow confirming a semantic ambiguity view by Donnellan, rather than denying Russell’s reading of definite descriptions also in the attributive case.

  12. 12.

    Christian Beyer detected the referential/attributive distinction in Edmund Husserl (Husserl 1987: 170ff, cited in Beyer 2001: 279–80).

    Whitehead 1920 discusses what we would today call ‘referential demonstrative descriptions’ and solves the problem via the demonstrative, which would refer even if the following description did not fit the case. But Donnellanian referential description is a much more intriguing and interesting case, concerning basic language dynamics. The idea of “solving” the problem via a demonstrative comes up, almost unnoticed, in many authors: «The man over there drinking champagne is happy tonight» (Kripke 1977: 256, my italics); «That man over there with champagne in his glass is happy» (Searle 1979: 196).

    I learned of Whitehead via Orilia 2009, who defends a descriptive solution to reference. If the F is the misdescription the speaker uses, Orilia posits another description, the G, which fits the referent. The speaker, he adds, believes that the F is identical to the G. However, this solution is of no help in the transfer of individuation, because the bridge description is not available to the audience.

  13. 13.

    In no way does Grice subscribe to a Humpty Dumpty theory of meaning.

  14. 14.

    The idea is already in Grice 1957 (but Grice still subscribed to it in 1989: 350).

  15. 15.

    See the “Prolegomena” to Grice 1989: 3–4.

  16. 16.

    Wittgenstein would not have held that speaker’s meaning is “generated” by speaker’s intention.

  17. 17.

    Many variants that are not in a speaker’s active repertoire are in her passive repertoire.

  18. 18.

    This is a case in which a demonstrative would be misleading, focusing on a particular vehicle or a particular version of a car, rather than on the model.

  19. 19.

    Linguistic training is mostly field learning.

  20. 20.

    Was it a language mistake or mistaking the case? The two aspects are not mutually independent.

  21. 21.

    Sperber and Wilson say «optimally» (19962: 198), but I prefer Simon’s «satisfactory» (Simon 1996 3: 27–28 and 119–120).

  22. 22.

    «We are dealing here with what are often called ‘cues,’ but ‘cues’ in this sense are quite different from ‘clues.’ […] For a cue, in this sense, may be operative without the individual realizing it or even suspecting it.» (Donnellan 1963: 404)

  23. 23.

    Penco 2017 insists on the reasonableness of most misdrescriptions.

  24. 24.

    Something alike also happens with names. An individual has a legal name that, in some countries, he can change, but others cannot. People can introduce nicknames, and these can become popular, but, even if complimentary, they do not replace legal names. That is what happens in Kripke’s famous example on mistaking Smith raking leaves for Jones. Only Smith seems to have the right to have his name changed.

  25. 25.

    See Trask 2009: 28–9. In Romance languages something similar happened to words originating from the Latin fortuna, from which fortuitous too originates.

  26. 26.

    Here are some other examples, someone with a history of shifts. Egregious, for instance, shifted from meaning “outstandingly good” to “outstandingly bad”. An example of an adverb whose meaning in Italian has been changed by mistake in the last 50 years is affatto, which originally meant by all means, and in the negative context, nient’affatto (by no means). Now affatto only means by no means. Glamour (in the sense of magic and enchanting) supposedly comes from grammar, and passed through attractive as applied to «women in the sense of dangerous temptresses», but vulgar, reaching «fashionable, sexy and utterly desirable» or attractive in a special (positive) way (Trask 2009: 6, my italics).

  27. 27.

    Syntactic changes are slow, and they too depend on use. The subjunctive mood is employed less and less, modal auxiliaries are used less, and where possible substituted by semimodals, for example, must by have to, and verbal inflection (especially for future tense) is substituted by adverbial terms. At the same time, there is evidence of a ‘densification’ of the information transferred by noun phrases increasing s-genitives, noun-noun sequences and acronyms. About all these changes there is a vast literature, one I have found very useful is Leech et al. 2009. Phonetic changes have come along with changes in orthography (as often happens in Italian). It is sufficient to read a text from the sixteenth century in order to get a sense of the phonetic dynamics of a language.

  28. 28.

    A prototypical use fixes a referent; a paradigmatic use offers a common way for referring to an individual or an object.

  29. 29.

    That is, ever since how a word connects with a thing became a philosophical concern. An interesting treatment of this issue and its intricacies can be found in Austin 1953.

  30. 30.

    Donnellan writes that «only» in the referential use can a speaker miss what she describes «by a mile», (1968: 209) but this is not so.

  31. 31.

    This precludes the possibility that descriptions refer and never denote, as suggested by Almog and Capuano.

  32. 32.

    Cf. Martí 2008 and Recanati 2013. Occasionally, a referential description can originate a nickname, if not a name. Between us, later, we can refer to the spy as ‘The Man Drinking a Martini,’ whether it is or not.

  33. 33.

    Kripke 1977’s view.

  34. 34.

    Bell connects the referential/attributive distinction to transparent/opaque context. The connection does not concern me here. Kripke 1977 quotes Bell 1973 in footnote 35, but he discards the proposal, claiming:

    [f]or reasons of space I have not treated these views here. But some of my arguments that Donnellan’s distinction is pragmatic apply against them also.

    Bell refers to Bach 1968, who, in arguing that noun phrases derive from relative clauses, extends to any of those the restrictive/non-restrictive (or appositive) proper of relative clauses. For a more up-to-date linguistic account of the restrictive/non-restrictive opposition, see Cinque 2008.

  35. 35.

    Devitt 2013.

  36. 36.

    Notwithstanding his criticism of Donnellan and his Russellianism, Kripke 1977 closes “Speaker’s reference and semantic reference” with:

    I think that the distinction between semantic reference and speaker’s reference will be of importance not only (as in the present paper) as a critical tool to block postulation of unwarranted ambiguities, but also will be of considerable constructive importance for a theory of language. In particular, I find it plausible that a diachronic account of the evolution of language is likely to suggest that what was originally a mere speaker’s reference may, if it becomes habitual in a community, evolve into a semantic reference. (1977: 291)

    Marco Santambrogio was the first to alert me to this passage.

References

  • J. Almog 2012 Referential uses and the foundations of direct reference (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 176–184).

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Almog 2014 Refential mechanism (New York/Oxford Oxford UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds 2012 Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (New York/Oxford Oxford UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine 397–400 Confessions (Eng tr. by J.K. Ryan New York Image Books 1960).

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Bach 1968 Nouns and Noun Phrases (Universals in Linguistic Theory E. Bach and R.T. Harms eds New York 1968:. 91–122).

    Google Scholar 

  • J.M. Bell 1973 What is referential opacity? (Journal of Philosophical Logic 2: 155–80).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • C. Beyer 2001 A neo-Husserlian theory of speaker’s reference (Erkenntnis

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Bezuidenhout 2013 “The (in)significance of the referential-attributive distinction” (in Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy A. Capone, M. Carapezza, F. Lo Piparo eds Berlin Springer).

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Capuano 2012 The ground zero of semnatics (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 7–29).

    Google Scholar 

  • H.-N. Castañeda 1977 On the philosophical foundations of the theory of communication: reference (in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, French, Uehling, and Wettstein eds, Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press:125–143).

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Cinque 2008 Two types of non-restrictive relatives (Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics O. Bonami & P. Cabredo Hofherr eds 7:. 99–137).

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Davidson 1986 A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs (in Philosophical Grounds of Rationality/Intentions, Categories, Ends (R. Grandy and R. Warner eds. Oxford Clarendon, pp. 157–74).

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Devitt 1974 Singular terms (The Journal of Philosophy 71: 183–205).

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Devitt 1981 Donnellan distinction (Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1):511–526).

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Devitt 2004 The Case for Referential Descriptions (in Descriptions and Beyond M. Reimer & A Bezuidenhout eds., Oxford at the UP, pp. 280–305).

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Devitt 2013 Three Methodological Flaws of Linguistic Pragmatism (in What is Said and What is Not. F. Domaneschi and C. Penco eds Stanford CSLI Publication: 285–300).

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Donnellan 1963 “Knowing What I Am Doing” (The Journal of Philosophy 60: 401–9).

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Donnellan 1966 Reference and Definite Descriptions (The Philosophical Review 75: 281–304).

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Donnellan 1968 Putting Humpty Dumpty Together Again (The Philosophical Review 77: 203–15).

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Donnellan 1978 Speaker Reference, Descriptions, and Anaphora (in Syntax and Semantics 9: Pragmatics P. Cole ed., New York Academic Press, pp. 47–68; reprinted in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. II Contemporary Philosophy of Language, rev. ed. 1979, pp. 28–43).

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Evans 1982 Varieties of reference (Oxford )

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Grice 1957 Meaning (The Philosophical Review 66: 377–388).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • P. Grice 1989 Studies in the way of words (Cambridge MA Harvard UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Horwich 1998 Meaning (Oxford Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Horwich 2005 Reflections on Meaning (Oxford Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Horwich 2012 Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy (New York Oxford UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl 1987 Husserliana – Edmund Husserl: Gesammelte Werke 26 : Vorlesungen über Bedeutungslehre. Sommersemester 1908 [Lectures on the doctrine of meaning: summer semester 1908.] U. Panzer ed (The Hague Nijhoff).

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Kaplan 2012 Having in mind (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 122–175).

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Kripke [1972] 1980 Naming and Necessity (in Semantics of Natural Language D. Davidson & G. Harman eds. Dordrecht: Reidel) pp. 253–355, 763–769 (reprinted in book format with added a Preface Oxford Blackwell 1980).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • S. Kripke [1973] 2013 Reference and Existence/The John Locke Lectures [1973] (Oxford/New York Oxford UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Kripke 1977 Speaker Reference and Semantic Reference (in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, French, Uehling, and Wettstein eds, Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press: 6–27).

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Leech, M. Hundt, C. Mair, and N. Smith 2009 Change in contemporary English/A grammatical study (Cambridge Cambridge UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Ludlow and S. Neale 2006 ‘Descriptions’ (in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language M. Devitt ed Oxford Blackwell: 288–313).

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Martí 2008 Direct reference and definite descriptions (Dialectica 62: 43–57).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • S. Neale 1990 Descriptions (Cambridge MA Mit Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Neale 2004 This, that, and the other (in Descriptions and Beyond M. Reimer & A Bezuidenhout eds., Oxford at the UP, pp. 68–182).

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Orilia 2009 Singular reference/A descriptivist perspective (Dordrecht Springer).

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Penco 2017 Donnellan’s misdescriptions and loose talk (In Reference and Representation in Language and Thought K. Korta and M. De Ponte eds Oxford Oxford UP: pp. 104–125).

  • F. Recanati 2013 Reference through mental files (in What is said and what is not F. Domaneschi and C. Penco eds Stanford CSLI Publications: 159–173).

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Reimer 1998 Donnellan’s Distinction/Kripke’s Test (Analysis 58: 89–100).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • B. Russell 1905 On denoting (Mind 14: 479–493).

    Google Scholar 

  • J.R. Searle 1979 Referential and attributive (The Monist 62: 190–208).

    Google Scholar 

  • H.A. Simon 19963 The sciences of the artificial (Cambridge MA MIT Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Sperber and M. Wilson 1986 Relevance/Communication and cognition (Oxford Blackwell).

    Google Scholar 

  • P.F. Strawson 1950 On referring (Mind 59: 320–344).

    Google Scholar 

  • R. L. Trask 2009 Why do languages change? (Cambridge Cambridge UP).

    Google Scholar 

  • A.N. Whitehead 1920 The concept of nature (Cambridge Cambridge UP)

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Wittgenstein 1953 [20094] Philosophischen Untersuchungen/Philosophical Investigations (Engl. tr. by G.E.M. Anscombe, P.M.S. Hacker and J. Schulte eds. Oxford Blackwell/Wiley).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paolo Leonardi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Leonardi, P. (2019). Descriptions in Use. In: Capone, A., Carapezza, M., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy: Part 2 Theories and Applications. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-00972-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-00973-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics