Skip to main content
Log in

Downside risk-neutral probabilities

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We show that there exists a probability measure under which the CAPM formula for expected returns holds for general utility functions and probability distributions. This probability measure, the “downside risk-neutral” measure, is adjusted to incorporate the effects of downside risk and higher degree risks. It thus belongs to the same family as the risk-neutral measure, which is also a risk-adjusted measure. Using risk preference theory, we interpret this change in probability measure in terms of risk substitution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An increase in second-degree risk is an increase in the dispersion of a distribution in the sense of mean-preserving spreads. An increase in third-degree risk (“downside risk”) is a transfer of risk to the left of the distribution which leaves the mean and variance unchanged. An increase in downside risk implies a lower third moment of the distribution, i.e., a lower skewness (Menezes et al. 1980). An increase in fourth-degree risk (“outer risk”) is a transfer of risk from the center toward the tails which leaves the mean, variance, and skewness unchanged.

  2. According to Dirac (1942), “Negative energies and probabilities (...) are well-defined concepts mathematically, like a negative sum of money, since the equations which express the important properties of energies and probabilities can still be used when they are negative”. According to Feynman (1987), negative probabilities are “entirely rational”, and “their use simplifies calculation and thought in a number of applications in physics”. Likewise, the purpose of downside risk-neutral probabilities is to provide an alternative pricing operator—unlike physical probabilities, they do not only measure the likelihood of an event.

  3. In Eq. (12), the expression \(1 - A(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _3} \left[ \tilde{c}_1-c_0\right] \) is strictly positive, as shown in Appendix A.

  4. The wealth portfolio comprises all assets that generate wealth in the economy. In practice, as emphasized by Roll (1977), it is doubtful whether investors can invest in the wealth portfolio, and indeed only imperfect proxies of this portfolio are used in empirical applications of the CAPM.

References

  • Dirac, P.A.M.: Bakerian lecture. The physical interpretation of quantum mechanics. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. 180, 1–40 (1942)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R.P.: Negative Probability. Quantum implications: essays in honour of David Bohm, pp. 235–248 (1987)

  • Harvey, C.R., Siddique, A.: Conditional skewness in asset pricing tests. J. Finance 55, 1263–1295 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimball, M.S.: Precautionary savings in the small and in the large. Econometrica 58, 53–73 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, L., Meyer, J.: Substituting one risk increase for another: a method for measuring risk aversion. J. Econ. Theory 148, 2706–2718 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Rustichini, R., Taboga, M.: Portfolio selection with monotone mean-variance preferences. Math. Finance 19, 487–521 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menezes, C., Geiss, C., Tressler, J.: Increasing downside risk. Am. Econ. Rev. 70, 921–932 (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  • Modica, S., Scarsini, M.: A note on comparative downside risk aversion. J. Econ. Theory 122, 267–271 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll, R.: A critique of the asset pricing theory’s tests. J. Financ. Econ. 4, 129–176 (1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the Associate Editor, an anonymous referee, as well as Georges Dionne, Christian Dorion, Mathieu Fournier, and Christian Gollier for useful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Chaigneau.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix A: Additional proofs

The expression\(1 - A(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _3} \left[ \tilde{c}_1-c_0\right] \)in Eq. (12)

We show that this expression is strictly positive.

First, consider the states s such that \(u^{(1)}(c_0) + u^{(2)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)>0\) and, therefore, \(\eta _{3,s}>0\) (given Eq. (3) and \(u^{(1)}>0\)), which implies \(\lambda _{3,s} \ge 0\). Then we have \(\lambda _{3,s} \left[ u^{(1)}(c_0) + u^{(2)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \right] \ge 0\). Dividing each term by \(u^{(1)}(c_0)\), which is strictly positive, and summing over these states s, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{s|\eta _{3,s}>0} \lambda _{3,s} \left[ 1 - A(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \right] \ge 0. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

Second, consider the states s such that \(u^{(1)}(c_0) + u^{(2)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)<0\), and therefore \(\eta _{3,s}<0\) (given Eq. (3) and \(u^{(1)}>0\)), which implies \(\lambda _{3,s} \le 0\). Then we have \(\lambda _{3,s} \left[ u^{(1)}(c_0) + u^{(2)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \right] \ge 0\). Dividing each term by \(u^{(1)}(c_0)\), which is strictly positive, and summing over these states s, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{s|\eta _{3,s}<0} \lambda _{3,s} \left[ 1 - A(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \right] \ge 0. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Third, because \(\lambda _{3,s} \left[ 1 - A(c_0) (c_s-c_0)\right] \ge 0\) for any s and \(1 - A(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \ne 0\) (otherwise \(\eta _{3,s}\) would not exist), both expressions on the left-hand sides of (17) and (18) will be equal to zero only if \(\lambda _{3,s}=0\) for all s, which would imply \(\sum _s\lambda _{3,s} \ne 1\), a contradiction. Therefore, at least one of the expressions on the left-hand sides of (17) and (18) is strictly positive, while the other is nonnegative. Adding up these two sums yields

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{s} \lambda _{3,s} \left[ 1 - A(c_0) (c_s-c_0) \right] =1 - A(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _3} \left[ \tilde{c}_1-c_0 \right] > 0. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

Let \(\tilde{m} \equiv \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \frac{ f(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)}{\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[f(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)]}\). The pricing kernel \(\tilde{m}\) in Proposition 2 is linear in \(\tilde{c}_1\). Since in addition \(\tilde{c}_1\) is linear in \(\tilde{R}^w\) (see Eq. (1)), we have \(\tilde{m} = a + b \tilde{R}^w\), and

$$\begin{aligned} a \equiv \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \frac{1+A(c_0)c_0}{1-A(c_0)(\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{c}_1]-c_0)}, \quad b \equiv \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \frac{-A(c_0)[w_0-c_0]}{1-A(c_0)(\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{c}_1]-c_0)}. \end{aligned}$$

Equation (11) can thus be rewritten as \(P_j=\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m} \tilde{x}^j]\). Dividing both sides by \(P_j\) gives \(1=\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m} \tilde{R}_j]\), where \(\tilde{R}_j \equiv \frac{\tilde{x}^j}{P_j}\) is the gross return of asset j. Rewrite this equation as

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m}]} = \mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{R}_j] + \frac{\mathrm{cov}^{\Lambda _3}(\tilde{m},\tilde{R}_j)}{\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m}]}. \end{aligned}$$

Using \(\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m}] = \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \), and substituting for \(\tilde{m}\), the equation above rewrites as

$$\begin{aligned} \mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{R}_j]-R_\mathrm{f} =- \frac{b \, \mathrm{cov}^{\Lambda _3}( \tilde{R}^w,\tilde{R}_j)}{\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m}]}. \end{aligned}$$
(19)

In particular, if the asset considered is the wealth portfolio with gross return \(\tilde{R}^w\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{R}^w]-R_\mathrm{f} = - \frac{b \, \mathrm{var}^{\Lambda _3}(\tilde{R}^w)}{\mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{m}]}. \end{aligned}$$
(20)

Equating Eqs. (19) and (20),

$$\begin{aligned} \mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{R}_j]-R_\mathrm{f} = \frac{\mathrm{cov}^{\Lambda _3}( \tilde{R}^w,\tilde{R}_j)}{\mathrm{var}^{\Lambda _3}(\tilde{R}^w)} \left[ \mathbb {E} ^{\Lambda _3}[\tilde{R}^w]-R_\mathrm{f} \right] . \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Appendix B: ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities

We start by introducing the family of ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities. Assume that u is of class \(C^i\), for an integer \(i \ge 2\). For given i and s, let \(\eta _{i,s}\) be defined implicitly as

$$\begin{aligned} u^{(1)}(c_s) \equiv \eta _{i,s} \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}. \end{aligned}$$
(21)

The sum on the right-hand side of Eq. (21) is a Taylor expansion of marginal utility of order \(i-2\) at \(c_0\), which only reflects the preferences for risks of degree \(i-1\) and lower. The left-hand side, the marginal utility of consumption, can be viewed as a Taylor series of marginal utility at \(c_0\), which reflects the preferences for all degrees of risks. We henceforth consider economies such that \(\eta _{i,s}\) exists for all s (\(\eta _{i,s}\) exists generically—except for \(\sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}=0\)).

Definition 2

Let \(\nu _i \equiv \sum _{s=1}^S p_s \eta _{i,s}\), and

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _{i,s} \equiv p_s \frac{ \eta _{i,s} }{\nu _i} = \frac{p_s \eta _{i,s}}{\sum _{s=1}^S p_s \eta _{i,s}}. \end{aligned}$$
(22)

The set \(\{ \lambda _{i,s} \}\) is the set of ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities, and \(\Lambda _i\) is the ith-degree risk-neutral probability measure.

The Radon–Nikodym derivative that yields ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities, \(\frac{\mathrm{d}\lambda _{i,s}}{\mathrm{d}p_s}=\frac{\eta _{i,s}}{\nu _i}\), is at any point proportional to the ratio of marginal utility of consumption to a Taylor expansion of marginal utility of order \(i-2\) at \(c_0\). Setting \(i=4\) yields outer risk-neutral probabilities.

The next Proposition establishes that the ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities not only coincide with physical probabilities in the limit, as \(i \rightarrow \infty \), but also for any i such that \(u^{(i)}=0\).

Proposition 4

The ith-degree risk-neutral probability measure, \(\Lambda _{\infty ,s}\), coincides with the physical probability measure for \(i \rightarrow \infty \). Moreover, for preferences such that \(u^{(i)}=0\), \(\Lambda _i\) coincides with the physical probability measure.

Proof

First, by analogy with Eq. (21), for any given s, let \(\eta _{\infty ,s}\) be defined implicitly as (\(\eta _{\infty ,s}\) exists generically—except for \(\sum _{k=0}^{\infty } \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}=0\)):

$$\begin{aligned} u^{(1)}(c_s) \equiv \eta _{\infty ,s} \sum _{k=0}^{\infty } \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}. \end{aligned}$$
(23)

Given that \(u^{(1)}\) is analytic at \(c_0\), the Taylor series of \(u^{(1)}\) give

$$\begin{aligned} u^{(1)}(c_s) = \sum _{k=0}^{\infty } \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}. \end{aligned}$$
(24)

Comparing with (23), this implies that \(\eta _{\infty ,s}=1\) for any s. Then Definition 2 implies that \(\lambda _{\infty ,s}=p_s\) for any s.

Second, suppose that \(u^{(i)}=0\), which implies that \(u^{(j)}=0\) for \(j \ge i\). Then, for any s, a Taylor expansion gives

$$\begin{aligned} u^{(1)}(c_s) = \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} u^{(k+1)}(c_0) (c_s-c_0)^{k}. \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Equation (21) then implies that \(\eta _{i,s}=1\) for any s, and Definition 2 implies that \(\lambda _{i,s} = p_s\) for any s. \(\square \)

We now show how to express the price of any asset with ith-degree risk-neutral probabilities. Let \(C_{k+1}(c_0) \equiv \frac{ u^{(k+1)}(c_0)}{u^{(1)}(c_0)} \) be the coefficient of absolute preference for the \(k+1\)th-degree risk at \(c_0\). A negative preference (i.e., an aversion) for the \(k+1\)th-degree risk implies that \(C_{k+1}(c_0)<0\). The price \(P_j\) of an asset with stochastic payoff \(\tilde{x}^j\) may be decomposed in the following terms.

Proposition 5

If u is of class \(C^i\), for a given integer \(i \ge 2\), then

$$\begin{aligned} P_j= & {} \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \frac{ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \tilde{x}^j \right] }{ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \right] } \end{aligned}$$
(26)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ \frac{ f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)}{ \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i}[f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)] } \tilde{x}^j \right] , \end{aligned}$$
(27)

where \(f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1) \equiv \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k}\).

Proof

Substituting \(u^{(1)}(c_s)\) from (21) in Eq. (2), the asset price \(P_j\) may be decomposed in the following terms:

$$\begin{aligned} P_j= & {} \sum _{s=1}^S p_s \left[ \beta \eta _{i,s} \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} \frac{ u^{(k+1)}(c_0)}{u^{(1)}(c_0)} (c_s-c_0)^{k} x_s^j \right] \nonumber \\= & {} \beta \nu _i \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \tilde{x}^j \right] \nonumber \\= & {} \beta \nu _i \left[ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \tilde{x}^j \right] \right] . \end{aligned}$$
(28)

Given that Eq. (28) must hold for any asset, including the risk-free asset whose payoff is \(x_s=1\) for all s and whose price is by definition of the gross risk-free rate \(R_\mathrm{f}\) equal to \(P_\mathrm{f}=\frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}}= \beta \nu _i \left[ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E}^{\Lambda _i} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \right] \right] . \end{aligned}$$
(29)

Substituting (29) in (28) gives Eq. (26). \(\square \)

By construction, for any \(i \ge 2\), the asset price in Proposition 5 is the same as the one in the standard stochastic discount factor formula in Eq. (2).

For preferences such that \(u^{(i)}=0\), \(\Lambda _i\) coincides with the physical probability measure (see Proposition 4), and the price of any asset with stochastic payoff \(\tilde{x}^j\) is

$$\begin{aligned} P_j = \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \frac{ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \tilde{x}^j \right] }{ \sum _{k=0}^{i-2} \frac{1}{k!} C_{k+1}(c_0) \mathbb {E} \left[ (\tilde{c}_1-c_0)^{k} \right] } = \frac{1}{R_\mathrm{f}} \mathbb {E} \left[ \frac{ f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)}{ \mathbb {E}[f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)] } \tilde{x}^j \right] , \end{aligned}$$
(30)

where \(f_i(c_0,\tilde{c}_1)\) is as in Proposition 5. For utility functions such as CRRA and CARA utility which are such that \(u^{(i)} \ne 0\) for any \(i \in (1,2,\ldots )\), the pricing kernel under physical probabilities can only be obtained in polynomial form as a Taylor series, with an infinite number of terms.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chaigneau, P., Eeckhoudt, L. Downside risk-neutral probabilities. Econ Theory Bull 8, 65–77 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00165-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00165-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation