Abstract
Social egalitarianism holds that individuals ought to have equal power over outcomes within relationships. Egalitarian philosophers have argued for this ideal by appealing to (sometimes implicit) features of political society. This way of grounding the social egalitarian principle renders it dependent on empirical facts about political culture. In particular, egalitarians have argued that social equality matters to citizens in political relationships in a way analogous to the value of equality in a marriage. In this paper, we show how egalitarian philosophers are committed to psychological premises, and then illustrate how to test the social egalitarian’s empirical claims. Using a nationally representative survey experiment, we find that citizens will sometimes prioritize equality over competing values, but that the weight of social equality diminishes when moving from personal to political cases. These findings raise questions for thinking about how to explain the normative significance of social equality.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.



Notes
“Relational equality” and “social equality” are sometimes used interchangeably in the literature. We will use “relational” to refer to equality among persons in specific relationships (including relationships with only two members) and “social” to refer to equality among larger collections of persons.
A relatively early entry in this literature is Hochschild 1986.
Such a view might be affirmed by civil libertarians, among others.
On the relationship between the value of equality in morality and politics, see, generally, Scheffler 2010.
Although this characterization meant to offer an ideal of marriage, it is also intended as a conceptual truth. If a relationship counts as a marriage, then it ought to meet this ideal. A challenge for the conceptual claim is that it will likely not fit with many groups’ experiences within seemingly real marriages. To deny that these relationships are marriages would be nontrivially revisionary.
Here Lister follows Ebels-Duggan 2008 (on marriage) and 2010 (on political community).
Our own cases, presented in the next section, will take a step toward filling this gap.
In brief: the social egalitarian could say that the relationships are different in a world of social equality, even if they do not appear different in any observable way. Although extensionally equivalent, two relationships have some morally relevant difference if one obtains in a world with social equality, and the other does not. This makes it appear that there is some hyperintensional variation between them, and that this variation bears moral significance. Perhaps the social egalitarian could develop the view in this way, but doing so would carry its own set of argumentative challenges.
References
Alesina, A., and G.M. Angeletos. 2005. Fairness and redistribution. American Economic Review 95 (4): 960–980.
Alesina, A., and E. Glaeser. 2004. Fighting poverty in the US and Europe: A world of difference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Anderson, E. 1999. What is equality? Ethics 109 (2): 287–337.
Ballard-Rosa, C., L. Martin, and K. Scheve. 2016. The structure of American income tax policy preferences. The Journal of Politics 79 (1): 1–16.
Bechtel, M.M., R. Liesch, and K.F. Sheve. 2018. Inequality and redistribution behavior in a give-or-take game. PNAS: 1–6.
Beerbohm, E., and R.W. Davis. 2017. The common good: A Buck-passing account. The Journal of Political Philosophy 25 (4): e60–e79.
Berker, S. 2013. Epistemic teleology and the separateness of propositions. Philosophical Review 122: 337–393.
Bohman, J., and H.S. Richardson. 2009. Liberalism, deliberative democracy, and ‘reasons that all can accept. Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (3): 253–274.
Brennan, J. 2016. Against democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Christiano, T. 2008. The constitution of equality: Democratic authority and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cramer, K. 2016. The politics of resentment: Rural consciousness in Wisconsin and the rise of Scott Walker. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Darwall, S. 2006. The second person standpoint. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Durante, R., L. Putterman, and J. van der Weele. 2014. Preferences for redistribution and perception of fairness: An experimental study. Journal of the European Economic Association 12 (4): 1059–1086.
Ebels-Duggan, K. 2008. Against beneficence: A normative account of love. Ethics 119 (1): 142–170.
Ebels-Duggan, K. 2010. The beginning of community: Politics in the face of disagreement. The Philosophical Quarterly 60 (238): 50–71.
Fisman, R., P. Jakiela, S. Kariv, and D. Markovits. 2015. The distributional preferences of an elite. Science 394 (6254): aab0096.
Gilens, M. 2012. Affluence and influence: Economic inequality and political power in America. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Hibbing, J.R., and E. Theiss-Morse. 2002. Stealth democracy: Americans’ beliefs about how government should work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jubb, R. 2015. The real value of equality. The Journal of Politics 77 (3): 679–691.
Kolodny, N. 2014a. Rule over none I: What justifies democracy? Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (3): 195–229.
Kolodny, N. 2014b. Rule over none II: Social equality and the justification of democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (4): 287–336.
Lister, A. 2013. Public reason and political community. Bloomsbury.
Lovett, F. 2009. Domination and distributive justice. The Journal of Politics 71 (3): 817–830.
Lovett, F. 2016. Civic republicanism and social justice. Political Theory 44: 687–696.
Mill, J.S. [1869] 1991. The Subjection of Women. Pp. 471–582 in John Gray (ed.) On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Neblo, M., K.M. Esterling, R.P. Kennedy, D.M.J. Lazar, and A.E. Sokey. 2010. Who wants to deliberate—And why? American Political Science Review 104 (3): 566–583.
O’neill, M. 2008. What should egalitarians believe? Philosophy & Public Affairs 36 (2): 119–156.
Quong, J. 2011. Liberalism without perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. 1996. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Scanlon, T.M. 2003. The diversity of objections to inequality. In The difficulty of tolerance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schaffer, J. 2008. The contrast-sensitivity of knowledge ascriptions. Social Epistemology 22 (3): 235–245.
Scheffler, S. 2005. Choice, circumstance, and the value of equality. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 4 (1): 5–28.
Scheffler, S. 2010. Equality and tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Scheffler, S. 2015. The practice of equality, pp. 21–44 in C. Fourie, F. Schuppert, and I. Wallimann-Helmer (eds.) Social Equality: On What it Means to be Equals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shiffrin, S. 2008. Promising, intimate relationships, and conventionalism. Philosophical Review 117 (40): 481–524.
Snedagar, J. 2015. Contrastivism about reasons and ought. Philosophy Compass 10 (6): 379–388.
Stilz, A. 2012. Why does the state matter morally? in Varieties of sovereignty and citizenship. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Viehoff, D. 2014. Democratic equality and political authority. Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (4): 337–375.
Walden, K. 2017. The relativity of ethical explanation, in Mark Timmons (ed.) Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics Vol. 6. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Williamson, T. 2007. The philosophy of philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Acknowledgments
For comments and suggestions, we’re grateful to Christopher Karpowitz, Lisa Argyle, Quin Monson, and Jessica Flanigan.
Funding
We received no external funding to conduct the research reported in this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflicting Interests
None.
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Davis, R.W., Preece, J. Individual Valuing of Social Equality in Political and Personal Relationships. Rev.Phil.Psych. 13, 177–196 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00527-8
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00527-8
Keywords
- Egalitarianism
- Ethics
- Marriage
- Rawls
- Justice