Skip to main content
Log in

DBS and Autonomy: Clarifying the Role of Theoretical Neuroethics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, we sketch how theoretical neuroethics can clarify the concept of autonomy. We hope that this can both serve as a model for the conceptual clarification of other components of PIAAAS (personality, identity, agency, authenticity, autonomy, and self) and contribute to the development of the empirical measures that Gilbert and colleagues [1] propose.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In Agid et al. [8], however, the quote is apparently mistranslated as “I am an electric doll” ([1], 4).

  2. On Korsgaard’s view, autonomy is one of two “essential characteristics of an agent,” with the other being efficacy (the degree to which one is successful in realizing the effects one intended to cause in action) ([24], 82). We thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  3. de Haan et al.’s emphasis on the significance affordances in this context is in line with recent experimental work in other neuropsychiatric contexts. See, for example, Thill et al. [29] and McBride et al. [30].

  4. They cite Goering [32], Gilbert and Cook [33], and Glannon and Ineichen [34] as supportive of this rationale.

  5. Of particular significance is the distinction between substantive and procedural relational views of autonomy ([39], §3). Substantive views place normative constraints on an agent’s point of view, requiring that she have (or not have) certain attitudes in order to count as autonomous. Procedural views, by contrast, require only that an agent’s attitudes were (or could have been) arrived at through an adequate process of reflection. We do not attempt to decided between these types of views, as our aim is not to adjudicate between different specifications of the conceptions that we have identified. We thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

  6. …Or at least, of her exercising it beyond the confines of her own mind. Some views of the mind conceptualize states of consciousness as mental acts ([45]).

  7. Self-determination pertains to “external, structural conditions” involving freedom and opportunity ([50], 17), and so captures important aspects of the relational conception of autonomy. Self-governance pertains to the ability decide and act in accordance with a Korsgaardian practical identity or self-conception (17-18), and so encompasses important aspects of both the traditional and experiential conceptions of autonomy. Self-authorization pertains to taking oneself to possess the “normative authority to be self-determining and self-governing” (18) in a way related to, among other things, practices of accountability and answerability (19), and so also involves aspects of the experiential and relational conceptions of autonomy.

References

  1. Gilbert, F., J.N.M. Viaña, and C. Ineichen. 2018a. Deflating the “DBS causes personality changes” bubble. Neuroethics: 1–17. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9373-8.

  2. Herzog, J., J. Reiff, P. Krack, K. Witt, B. Schrader, and D. Mu. 2003. Manic episode with psychotic symptoms induced by subthalamic nucleus stimulation in a patient with Parkinson’s disease. Movement Disorders 18 (11): 1382–1384. https://doi.org/10.1002/mds.10530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Klaming, L., and P. Haselager. 2013. Did my brain implant make me do it? Questions raised by DBS regarding psychological continuity, responsibility for action and mental competence. Neuroethics 6 (3): 527–539. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9093-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Baylis, F. 2013. “I am who I am”: On the perceived threats to personal identity from deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics 6 (3): 513–526. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9137-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Goering, S., E. Klein, D.D. Dougherty, and A.S. Widge. 2017. Staying in the loop: Relational agency and identity in next-generation DBS for psychiatry. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 59–70. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1320320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Gilbert, F., E. Goddard, J.N.M. Viaña, A. Carter, and M. Horne. 2017. I miss being me: Phenomenological effects of deep brain stimulation. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 96–109. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1320319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Schüpbach, M., M. Gargiulo, M.L. Welter, L. Mallet, C. Behar, J.L. Houeto, et al. 2006. Neurosurgery in Parkinson disease: A distressed mind in a repaired body? Neurology 66 (12): 1811–1816. https://doi.org/10.1212/01.wnl.0000234880.51322.16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Agid, Y., M. Schüpbach, M. Gargiulo, L. Mallet, J.L. Houeto, C. Behar, et al. 2006. Neurosurgery in Parkinson’s disease: The doctor is happy, the patient less so? Journal of Neural Transmission 70 [Suppl]: 409–414. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-211-45295-0_61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2015. Effects of deep brain stimulation on the lived experience of obsessive-compulsive disorder patients: In-depth interviews with 18 patients. PLoS One 10 (8): 1–29. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0135524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Vukov, J.M. 2017. Three kinds of agency and closed-loop neural devices. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 90–91. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1320324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Lázaro-Muñoz, G., A.L. McGuire, and W.K. Goodman. 2017. Should we be concerned about preserving agency and personal identity in patients with adaptive deep brain stimulation systems? AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 73–75. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1320337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Beauchamp T.L., and Childress J.F. 2013. Principles of biomedical ethics. 7th edition. New York: Oxford University Press

  13. DeGrazia, D. 2005. Human identity and bioethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Dworkin, G. 1988. The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Dworkin, G. 1976. Autonomy and behavior control. Hastings Center Report 6 (1): 23–28. https://doi.org/10.2307/3560358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Frankfurt, H.G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20. https://doi.org/10.2307/2024717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Gibert, S.H. 2017. Closed-loop deep brain stimulation and its compatibility with autonomous agency. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 88–90. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1320326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Eslinger, P.J., and A.R. Damasio. 1985. Severe disturbance of higher cognition after bilateral frontal lobe ablation: Patient EVR. Neurology 35 (12): 1731–1741. https://doi.org/10.1212/WNL.35.12.1731.

  19. Cabrera, L.Y., E.L. Evans, and R.H. Hamilton. 2014. Ethics of the electrified mind: Defining issues and perspectives on the principled use of brain stimulation in medical research and clinical care. Brain Topography 27 (1): 33–45. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10548-013-0296-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Pacherie, E. 2008. The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition 107 (1): 179–217. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.09.003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Pacherie, E. 2007. The sense of control and the sense of agency. Psyche 13 (1): 1–30. https://jeannicod.ccsd.cnrs.fr/ijn_00352565. Accessed 7 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bayne, T. 2008. The phenomenology of agency. Philosophy Compass 3 (1): 182–202. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00122.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Kriegel, U. 2015. The varieties of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Korsgaard, C.M. 2009. Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Korsgaard, C.M. 1996. The sources of normativity. Edited by O. O’Neill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  26. Prigatano, G.P. 2009. Anosognosia: Clinical and ethical considerations. Current Opinion in Neurology 22 (6): 606–611. https://doi.org/10.1097/WCO.0b013e328332a1e7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2013. The phenomenology of deep brain stimulation-induced changes in OCD: An enactive affordance-based model. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7: 1–14. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Gibson, J.J. 1986 [1979]. The ecological approach to visual perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Thill, S., D. Caligiore, A.M. Borghi, T. Ziemke, and G. Baldassarre. 2013. Theories and computational models of affordance and mirror systems: An integrative review. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 37 (3): 491–521. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2013.01.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. McBride, J., P. Sumner, S.R. Jackson, N. Bajaj, and M. Husain. 2013. Exaggerated object affordance and absent automatic inhibition in alien hand syndrome. Cortex 49 (8): 2040–2054. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2013.01.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Kellmeyer, P., T. Cochrane, O. Müller, C. Mitchell, T. Ball, J.J. Fins, and N. Biller-Andorno. 2016. The effects of closed-loop medical devices on the autonomy and accountability of persons and systems. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (4): 623–633. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180116000359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Goering, S. 2015. Stimulating autonomy: DBS and the Prospect of choosing to control ourselves through stimulation. AJOB Neuroscience 6 (4): 1–3. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2015.1106274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Gilbert, F., and M. Cook. 2015. Are predictive brain implants an indispensable feature of autonomy? Bioethica Forum 8 (4): 121–127. http://www.bioethica-forum.ch/content/e_Archive.php. Accessed 7 June 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Glannon, W., and C. Ineichen. 2016. Philosophical aspects of closed-loop neuroscience. In Closed loop neuroscience, ed. A. El Hady, 259–270. New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  35. Gilbert, F. 2015. A threat to autonomy? The intrusion of predictive brain implants. AJOB Neuroscience 6 (4): 4–11. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2015.1076087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Gilbert, F., T. O’Brien, and M. Cook. 2018b. The effects of closed-loop brain implants on autonomy and deliberation: What are the risks of being kept in the loop? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 27 (2): 316–325. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180117000640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Christman, J. 2004. Relational autonomy, Liberal individualism, and the social constitution of selves. Philosophical Studies 117 (1/2): 143–164 https://doi.org/www.jstor.org/stable/4321441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Westlund, A.C. 2009. Rethinking relational autonomy. Hypatia 24 (4): 26–49. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2009.01056.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Stoljar, N. 2018. Feminist perspectives on autonomy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/feminism-autonomy/. Accessed 7 June 2019.

  40. Vidal, F. 2018. Phenomenology of the locked-in syndrome: An overview and some suggestions. Neuroethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9388-1.

  41. Fernández-Espejo, D., and A.M. Owen. 2013. Detecting awareness after severe brain injury. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 14: 801–809. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn3608.

  42. Monti, M. M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M. R., Boly, M., Pickard, J. D., Tshibanda, L., … Laureys, S. (2016). Willful modulation of brain activity in disorders of consciousness, 579–589. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa0905370.

  43. Naci, L., M.M. Monti, D. Cruse, A. Kübler, B. Sorger, R. Goebel, B. Kotchoubey, and A.M. Owen. 2012. Brain-computer interfaces for communication with nonresponsive patients. Annals of Neurology 72 (3): 312–323. https://doi.org/10.1002/ana.23656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Schnakers, C., J.T. Giacino, M. Løvstad, D. Habbal, M. Boly, H. Di, et al. 2015. Preserved covert cognition in noncommunicative patients with severe brain injury? Neurorehabilitation and Neural Repair 29 (4): 308–317. https://doi.org/10.1177/1545968314547767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Brentano, F. 2012 [1874]. Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Edited by O. Kraus, L. L. McAlister. Translated by A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, & L. L. McAlister. London and New York: Routledge.

  46. Morar, N., and J.A. Skorburg. 2017. Relational agency: Yes—But how far? Vulnerability and the moral self. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 83–85. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2017.1326409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Müller, S., M. Bittlinger, and H. Walter. 2017. Threats to neurosurgical patients posed by the personal identity debate. Neuroethics 10 (2): 299–310. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-017-9304-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Levy, N. 2011. Enhancing authenticity. Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (3): 308–318. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5930.2011.00532.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Parens, E. 2005. Authenticity and ambivalence: Toward understanding the enhancement debate. The Hastings Center Report 35 (3): 34–41. https://doi.org/10.2307/3528804.

  50. Mackenzie, C. 2014. Three dimensions of autonomy: A relational analysis. In Autonomy, oppression, and gender, ed. A. Veltman and M. Piper, 15–41. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  51. Gallagher, S. 2018. Deep brain stimulation, self and relational autonomy. Neuroethics 107: 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0913016107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Gallagher, S. 2013. A pattern theory of self. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7: 1–7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Dings, R., and L. de Bruin. 2016. Situating the self: Understanding the effects of deep brain stimulation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (2): 151–165. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-015-9421-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2017. Becoming more oneself? Changes in personality following DBS treatment for psychiatric disorders: Experiences of OCD patients and general considerations. PLoS One 12 (4): 1–27. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0175748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Raz, J. 1994. Multiculturalism: A Liberal perspective. In Ethics in the public domain: Essays in the morality of law and politics, 170–191. Oxford: Clarendon Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198260691.003.0008.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research for this article was funded by a BRAIN Initiative grant from the U.S. National Institute of Mental Health of the National Institutes of Health, Award Number R01MH114854 (to G.L.M.). The views expressed are those of the authors alone and do not necessarily reflect views of the NIH, Baylor College of Medicine, or Rice University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabriel Lázaro-Muñoz.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zuk, P., Lázaro-Muñoz, G. DBS and Autonomy: Clarifying the Role of Theoretical Neuroethics. Neuroethics 14 (Suppl 1), 83–93 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-019-09417-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-019-09417-4

Keywords

Navigation