Introduction

The American paleontologist Niles Eldredge, famous co-proponent of the theory of punctuated equilibrium, recently asserted that “(e)volutionary biology is a notoriously diffuse field of scientific inquiry” (Eldredge 2008; p. 10). Ten years after that statement, the idea seems to hold as the discipline comprises a plural landscape of multiple co-existent conceptual frameworks and strenuous voices that disagree on the nature and scope of ‘evolutionary theory’ (e.g., Oyama 1986; West-Eberhard 2003; Kirschner and Gerhart 2005; Dieckmann and Doebeli 2005; Lynch 2007; Hoekstra and Coyne 2007; Duboule 2010; Laubichler 2010; Wagner 2011; Depew and Weber 2011; Nei 2013; Jablonka and Lamb 2014; Laland et al. 2014, 2015; Futuyma 2015; Pavličev and Wagner 2015; Jaeger et al. 2015; Pievani 2016a; Eldredge et al. 2016; Welch 2017; Charlesworth et al. 2017). Within this plural landscape, a public debate is gaining ground (see Laland et al. 2014): whether a ‘new’ conceptual framework, i.e., the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES), is needed to extend or go beyond the boundaries and explanatory power of the Standard Evolutionary Theory (SET), the purported direct heir of the Modern Synthesis (MS; in contrast, see Stoltzfus 2017).

This idea is not precisely novel (it is present, for example, in Waddington 1969; Gould 1980; Stanley 1981; Bonner 1982; Eldredge 1985; Wicken 1987; Endler and McLellan 1988): throughout the twentieth-century, numerous calls for a ‘New Synthesis’ came from diverse, manifold, and—in some cases—unrelated paleontological and neontological trenches [see Depew and Weber 2013 for a brief overview; see also Callebaut 2010 and Peterson 2016; for a discussion about Niles Eldredge’s ‘Hierarchy Theory of Evolution’ (HTE), a previous attempt to extend the MS from palaeontological grounds and the study of macroevolution, in relation to the concepts and themes espoused in the EES, see Fábregas-Tejeda and Vergara-Silva 2018]. But this time, the framework known as EESFootnote 1 portrays itself in a different light with a far-reaching purview to counteract the explanatory shortcomings of the SET (Laland et al. 2014, 2015). The ‘intellectual movement’ that publicly started as a published article in the journal Evolution authored by the Italian-American evolutionary biologist and philosopher Massimo Pigliucci—in 2007, where the term ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis’ was coined—soon led to a workshop organized by Gerd B. Müller and Pigliucci at the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research (Klosterneuburg, Austria), out of which a (now widely discussed) volume arose (see Pigliucci and Müller 2010a). These events were followed by the publication of several articles (e.g., Craig 2010; Noble et al. 2014; Laland et al. 2014; Pigliucci and Finkelman 2014; Noble 2015; Laland et al. 2015; Pievani 2016b) and the organization of a number of scientific meetings dealing with the contours, limitations, challenges and philosophical debates raised by the so-called EES. So far, the EES has exhibited a constellation of social features not seen before in other calls to extend the MS and/or the SET, mainly reflected in considerable institutional and financial support—for instance, the award of an important grant provided by the John Templeton Foundation in 2016 to a group of international scholars, led by Kevin Laland (University of St Andrews) and Tobias Uller (Lund University), to ‘put the predictions of the EES to the test’ (see, e.g., http://synergy.st-andrews.ac.uk/ees/the-project/; http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/the-project/summary-of-our-research/). Further interdisciplinary projects, press attention (e.g., Pennisi 2016, 2008; Whitfield 2008; Grant 2010; Zimmer 2016; Kiger 2016) and the involvement of a large group of evolutionary biologists, philosophers of science and social scientists from a wide-range of academic backgrounds that share explanatory goals and agendas (see http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/people/) strengthen this picture, at the same time epistemological and sociological.

Nevertheless, lingering philosophical questions remain for historians and philosophers of biology to address: What is the nature of the ongoing change and what type of conceptual architectures are to be expected from the EES? What exactly does the EES ‘stand for,’ and what would be entailed by resignifications of concepts already defined in/by the SET? In this article, we will outline the different philosophical proposals that have emerged so far as attempts to conceptualize the emerging structure of the EES and its position and significance within contemporary evolutionary biology. Here, we should acknowledge that the evaluation of the merit, utility or intellectual contribution of the variety of models combined under the label of the EES is an important subject that nevertheless lies beyond the scope of this article. That discussion is being actively held between scientists defending that standpoint (e.g., Laland et al. 2015; Müller 2017) and their opponents (e.g., Welch 2017; Futuyma 2017), which includes assessments of specific aspects of the EES (e.g., a critical appraisal of the notion of ‘reciprocal causation’ in the EES is presented by Svensson 2018). After recounting the philosophical proposals that have been propounded to conceptualize the emerging structure of the EES, we will put forward an alternative interpretation and further discuss the topic of explanatory integration in this conceptual framework, focusing on evolutionary developmental biology (Evo-Devo sensu Müller 2007a) as a case study. The last point should be considered preliminary, though, pending analysis in the context of recent proposals of a ‘theory of theory integration’ (see Laubichler et al. 2018) which have paid special attention to evolutionary biology-related concepts and issues. We will begin with Massimo Pigliucci’s personal account and philosophical standpoint about the EES.

The ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis’ (EES): what is the nature of the ongoing change and what type of conceptual architectures are to be expected?

A common held idea within the minds of natural scientists, although severely criticized by historians and philosophers of science, is that theoretical syntheses not only have been accomplished throughout the complex histories of their particular disciplines, but also represent the paragon of something desirable and worth-pursuing in the future (Casanueva and Martínez 2014), i.e., the embodiment of a ‘rational success’ (see, for instance, Sidlauskas et al. 2010). For models of continuous scientific change, the cases of intertheoretic reduction or assimilation with mild corrections receive positive assessments because, by subsuming previous achievements under novel, wider frameworks, science can develop by successive augmentations and unifications (Casanueva and Martínez 2014). This is the mindset glanced in Massimo Pigliucci’s account of the conceptual history—and uninterrupted expansion of the conceptual repertoire—of ‘evolutionary theory’, from Darwinism to the recent discussions and reevaluations put forth by the EES (see Pigliucci 2009). In that article, Pigliucci embraced a position that we call ‘unicity of evolutionary thought’: for him, evolutionary biology is composed of a single conceptual framework cemented by the ideas of Charles Robert Darwin and Alfred Russell Wallace that has been modified, refined, expanded and assembled in a step-wise manner during historically important instantiations (i.e., ‘Neo-Darwinism,’ ‘Modern Synthesis’ and ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis’), represented as a nested set of ellipses in Pigliucci’s original diagram.Footnote 2 In his own words: “(…) evolutionary biology has not undergone a paradigm shift since Darwin and Wallace’s work” (Pigliucci 2009; p. 219; a key viewpoint also underscored in Pigliucci 2007). By explicitly embracing Kuhnian notions, Pigliucci argues that evolutionary biologists have reacted to various minor crises by means of augmenting the preexisting framework, constructing new floors in their robust structure, without shaking or undermining its Darwinian foundations (Pigliucci 2007). Likewise, in recent times Pigliucci has stated that no methodological, observational or semantic incommensurability exists between the EES and the ‘Darwinian Paradigm’ (see the talk ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis and paradigm shifts’ available at his website https://platofootnote.wordpress.com/talks/; see also Pigliucci 2018). According to this view, contemporary evolutionary biology (and the EES debate within it) is seen as an unscathed edifice of puzzle-solving ‘normal science’. Hence, in our interpretation, Pigliucci’s answer to the question posed earlier is that we are in the wake of the newest instantiation of a persisting Kuhnian paradigm.

This vantage point, in its extreme form, grants that there is but ‘one Theory of Evolution’ in the twenty-first century, bequeathed by the sustained efforts of multiple scientists, whose conceptual contributions can be, in principle, aligned with unbroken historical continuity. Veiled in this alleged consecutive advancement of ‘evolutionary theory’ could lie an unrecognized projection of how things ought to unfold in the future. Citing the last sentence of Pigliucci’s 2009 article: “Because of the very nature of science, there is no pretense at all that the third ellipse will be the end of the story”; mirroring the past, new instantiations of ‘evolutionary theory’ will be defined and delimited in the horizon of future ideas, phenomena to be studied and fields of inquiry, suggesting an endless spiral—progressive but perfectible—of conceptual expansion (see Fig. 1). However, this is an over-simplistic view of the history, present state and future projections of evolutionary biology as a scientific discipline (see also Delisle 2018; p. 158): history cannot be used to accurately predict the future (see Gaddis 2002) and, as robust historiography of science shows, scientific knowledge does not accumulate in a linear and progressive fashion (e.g., Raj 2013; for a contextualized example in the history of evolutionary biology, see Amundson 2005).Footnote 3

Fig. 1
figure 1

Image conceived by Fátima Sofía Ávila-Cascajares and Alejandro Fábregas-Tejeda; image design by Casandra Lizbeth Méndez-Martínez, Diana Martínez Almaguer and Julio César Montero Rojas (color figure online)

Conceptual representation, based on Pigliucci (2009), of the continuous expansion of ‘evolutionary theory’ in terms of ideas, phenomena studied, and fields of inquiry. The conceptual elements portrayed in the diagram reflect Pigliucci’s original choices (2009)—even though we strongly disagree with the epistemic location of Natural History, Paleontology and other entities—, with the only exception of disbanding and rewording the pairings of concepts (evolvability and modularity; plasticity and genetic accommodation). Instead of depicting the alleged consecutive advancement using a nested hierarchy of ellipses (see Pigliucci 2009), we chose the graphic representation of an endless spiral of expansion. The multicolored line demarcates the boundaries of the historically important instantiations of evolutionary theory (i.e., Darwinism, Modern Synthesis, Extended Evolutionary Synthesis). The yellow set represents Darwin’s theory; the green set is the Modern Synthesis; the blue set corresponds to the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis; and the purple set enclosed in dotted lines hint at possible future expansions of evolutionary theory. The relative distance between the elements is not intended to reflect closer conceptual ties; likewise, the relative order of appearance of the elements throughout the spiral does not imply chronological developments.

At the same time, many historians and philosophers would disagree with the portrayal of ‘persisting paradigm’ that Pigliucci ascribes to evolutionary biology—first of all, as has been argued many times, Kuhnian notions such as ‘paradigm’ or ‘exemplar’ prove to be flawed, or at least very difficult to apply, for the case of biology (see, e.g., Lewens 2016; Peterson 2016). Philosophers of biology such as Telmo Pievani (2012) openly disagree with the characterization of current evolutionary theory as a Kuhnian paradigm on the grounds that no serious anomalies have accrued in the last century, and that there is no tangible ‘dogmatic crystallization’ or ‘hardening’ that announces a major crisis and a subsequent paradigm shift. Instead, Pievani (2012, 2016a) argues that is commonplace in the field of evolutionary biology to solve and understand new problems and apparent exceptions mainly through integrative explanations, fine adjustments of the breadth of application of established forms of explanation to distinct empirical domains, novel calculations of the relative frequency of occurrence of evolutionary patterns, and by means of updating the evolutionist’s theoretical tool-kit and plodding along experimental novelties. That means that “(…) the dynamics of growth and evolution of the theory is based on processes of theoretical extension and empirical enlargement of an elastic set of explanations already consolidated but constantly needing adjustments and integrations” (Pievani 2012; p. 214). Furthermore, for this author the notion of a ‘scientific research program’ (SRP; sensu Lakatos 1978) best captures the intricacies of the non-static set of articulated explanations of evolutionary biology (Pievani 2012). In contrast to the discontinuous shifts of Kuhnian paradigms, Lakatosian scientific research programs change in a continuous fashion and allow for amendments and processes of updating (Suman 2016). Pievani (2012) also makes the case that the ongoing transition from the MS to an EES could be best represented as a progressive reformation—and not a blunt substitution—of a prior evolutionary research program with a different one that displays an extended Neo-Darwinian core, surrounded by a brand-new protective belt of epistemic assumptions and auxiliary hypotheses with a pluralistic and integrative explanatory approach. The core of the evolutionary biology SRP known as MS is depicted by Pievani as the genetic and populational theory of natural selection; accordingly, three major methodological postulates comprise the external protective belt: phyletic gradualism, extrapolationism from microevolution to macroevolution, and stringent adaptationism (Pievani 2012; for a contrasting characterization, see Futuyma 2015). Pievani therefore thinks that the EES entails a steady and irreversible transformation of the architecture of the previous SRP (i.e., a new protective belt and an expanded core), and not merely a superficial styling on marginal points of a hardened structure. In that sense, the structure of the new SRP would contain profound conceptual novelty and pluralistic frameworks while remaining compatible with the core of the MS (Pievani 2012).

A similar version of that view, which instead portrays the EES as an alternative Lakatosian research program to the SET—and not the reformation of such theoretical assemblage—was expounded and discussed during the 2016 meeting ‘New trends in evolutionary biology: biological, philosophical and social science perspectives’ held at the Royal Society of London, and is now reaching for consensus among the international community of scientists and philosophers that support the EES movement. At the aforementioned meeting, during the first round table discussion moderated by the British philosopher of science Nancy Cartwright (8 November 2016), Kevin Laland stated that, in his opinion, the EES is an alternative (and complementary) Lakatosian research program to the SET (audio recordings of the presentations are available at https://royalsociety.org/science-events-and-lectures/2016/11/evolutionary-biology/). This is the discursive presentation of the EES that was hinted in Laland et al. (2015), and the one that explicitly appears in the recently inaugurated website of the EES, linked with the project financed by the Templeton Foundation (see http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/).

It is important to stress that, for the current state of affairs in the plural landscape of evolutionary biology, characterizing the EES with Lakatosian schemes is not a move free of drawbacks. According to the evaluative typology Lakatos (1978) proposed for SRPs, a program can be progressive during a limited timeframe if it is able to make successful predictions and increase the number of statements and hypotheses with empirical content; on the contrary, a program can be degenerative if it only resorts to ad hoc explanations to account for novel observations. Notwithstanding that apparently clear-cut distinction, Lakatos emphasized that tables can be turned at any moment: a successful program may start to degenerate and a competing program could overcome a rough patch, becoming progressive once again. Moreover, at this point it is necessary to remember that the methodology proposed by Lakatos is exclusively retrospective: it provides neither forward-looking assessments of present competing scientific research programs, nor delineates strong criteria to rationally conduct the business of theory appraisal (for an analysis, see Hacking 1979). His friend and colleague, Paul Feyerabend, fiercely criticized Lakatosian methodology—in the book Against Method (1975)—because it ‘could not function as a good device’ for advising on current scientific work. For Lakatos himself, the progressiveness or degeneracy of a SRP could only be asserted through historiographical work; thus, by resorting to Lakatosian schemes, the proponents of the EES cannot claim that the SET should be abandoned because their conceptual framework is, in some sense, superior (as was hinted in Laland et al. 2014; a position that was later changed in Laland et al. 2015), if they wish to remain congruent with the philosophical standpoint they openly chose. Furthermore, even though the entire list of predictions (delineated in Laland et al. 2015) set to be tested by the Templeton Foundation’s project turned out to be successful, the proponents of the EES cannot claim that their research program will entail future achievements and that it is progressive (for Lakatos, that is something only historians can decide). According to Lakatos, successful predictions do not guarantee, by any means, future successes: the EES can start in a progressive path and end up in disparagement, being overpassed by a renewed SET. In Lakatosian terms, then, the EES movement could prove to be transitory, and subject to the rhetoric and sociological contexts of evolutionary biology that surely will unfold in the next few years.

The Modern Synthesis was articulated and elaborated around the time a strong and over-arching tradition of philosophy of science (i.e., logical empiricism) was gaining groundFootnote 4 (for historical and philosophical overviews, see Smocovitis 1996; Callebaut 2010, respectively). Although not mentioned or recognized very often, the architects of the MS and logical empiricists shared epistemological commitments (Delisle 2009): ideals of a unified science and compact explanatory structures capable of dealing with numerous and multifarious phenomena. There are communicating vessels between this philosophical heritage and the interpretations that regard the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis as a unification—a new compact explanatory structure—of disparate concepts, puzzling phenomena and scientific disciplines, such as the vision portrayed in Fig. 1 (for a discussion, vide supra). Framing the EES as a persisting Kuhnian paradigm or as an alternative Lakatosian research program are not the only possible philosophical avenues to think about theoretical change or the possible interpretations of what the label ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis’ stands forFootnote 5 and what resignifications may entail. We think that maybe the right metaphors of scientific change are not at play. It is relatively easy to use worn-out notions such as ‘paradigm’ or ‘scientific research program’. A bigger challenge for philosophers and historians of biology is to come up with different metaphors or models of scientific change to comprehensively characterize the structure of scientific frameworks. We agree with Love (2010) that there is no ‘one and only’ correct way of thinking about evolutionary theory (or theories, we may add) and that epistemological perspectives should be discussed in a ‘pluralistic stance’ (sensu Kellert et al. 2006), gauging the alternatives with its advantages, disadvantages, biases and heuristic values. Contrary to the pursuit for the hegemonic ascent of a single view to apprehend the EES, we prefer alternative images in which pluralism can thrive (see Casanueva 2016). In what follows, we propose one of such outlooks in order to start the discussion, though we do not claim that it is an unblemished view.

Alternative interpretations of the ‘emerging structure’ of the EES

For evolutionary biologists, there is a pervasive tendency to think that “evolutionary theory [here referring to the theoretical structure or the central tenets of the MS] is a cohesive unit, which maintains a single structural packaging of its theoretical content” (Love 2013; p. 327; text inside brackets added). On the other hand, many philosophers of biology have contended that the MS cannot be represented as a single comprehensive scientific theory (e.g., Wassermann 1981; Burian 1988; Callebaut 2010; Love 2013). Werner Callebaut (2010) characterized the ‘evolution of evolutionary thinking’, since the onset of the MS, as an open-ended dialectical history of simultaneous unifying and disunifying tendencies: this comment bolsters the view that it is more suitable to think of the MS as a “flexibly structured network of concepts and models” (p. 457) rather than as a bona fide theory, as they are usually conceptualized by classical philosophical traditions. Accordingly, we do not see the EES as a single theory or as something akin to a new compact explanatory structure revolving around a unified core (something Pigliucci 2009, Fig. 1 and the other portrayals of the EES revised before seem to imply; see also Reiss 2012). The invocation of spatial containment metaphors to depict the EES (remarkably, the image of a nested set of ellipses or its variations that presume that what is needed to extend the MS/SET is merely to enlarge its conceptual bucket) is followed by another unwanted assumption: that its theory structure is relatively uncomplicated, consisting of an organized system with a central core and some regional satellites, although their specifics relations remain unstated (Love 2013; see also Love 2017 for other critiques of the inadequacy of spatial containment metaphors to characterize evolutionary biology).

Alternatively, we think that the mature structure of the EES might not be characterized by a new harmonious set of perfectly consistent theories (in contrast to what has once been claimed for the case of the MS, see Mayr 1963; p. 8). Instead, we propose the image of a large network of models and interweaved representations that, instantiated in diverse practices, are connected and related in multiple ways.Footnote 6 In their review of Pigliucci and Müller (2010a), Handschuh and Mitteroecker (2012) informally suggested that the gestation and maturation of the EES, in an analogy to the historical development of the MS, can follow defined stages: after the expansion of the remodeled MS framework by adding concepts of innovative research fields (i.e., the second stage of their periodization), a new core, much more diverse and thus much looser in interdependency, could be accepted by consensus, “integrating the spectrum of concepts to a weblike theoretical network” (p. 19). This view is different from ours because we think that the EES could be articulated around a paraconsistent network (or group of networks) of evolutionary models, practices and representation systems, with edges and nodes that change their position and centrality as a consequence of the co-construction and stabilization of facts and historical discussions revolving around the epistemic goals of evolutionary biology.

Units and goals in the epistemology of the EES

Epistemic goals are complex scientific problems consisting of a set of related questions (Brigandt 2010). Ingo Brigandt (2010) recognizes these are synonyms to Alan Love’s notion of ‘problem agenda’ (see Love 2008, 2010). Love (2010) has suggested an “erotetic (pertaining to questioning) structure for evolutionary theory, which characterizes a synthesis in terms of multiple problem agendas exhibiting complex but coordinating relationships” (p. 404). Each epistemic goal or problem agenda is associated with ‘criteria of adequacy’, which, given current empirical and conceptual background knowledge, set standards for what counts as an adequate solution (i.e., what shape a satisfactory explanation has to take), thus forming the overall explanans for a particular explanandum (Brigandt 2010). For example, an epistemic goal for Evo-Devo (or, as some would claim, for contemporary evolutionary biology as a whole) is the explanation of evolvability (Wagner 2015; Nuño de la Rosa 2017) and evolutionary novelties (Brigandt 2010; Brigandt and Love 2010, 2012). In contrast, as stated by Pigliucci and Müller (2010b), a primary goal for an ‘extended synthesis’—and/or for the EES—is to provide a causal-mechanistic account of phenotypic evolution. To be sure, an epistemic goal for the EES sensu Laland et al. (2015) is to give a mechanistic explanation of the origin and maintenance of functional and selectable phenotypic variation (with its genetic and non-genetic sources). Another important epistemic goal for the EES is to understand the constructive roles organisms play shaping their own development and evolution, and how they change their environments (through niche construction and other ontogenetic processes) in evolutionary meaningful ways (Laland et al. 2015).

In our scheme, classic Neo-Darwinian elements (e.g., natural selection) would not be at the center or core of this imagined diffuse network (because it will be devoid of one) but would most likely be hubs in a more distributed and inclusive conceptual system of connections (for a different rebuttal of the idea of ‘core’ in evolutionary biology, see Love 2013). In this view, some local regions of the dynamical network(s)Footnote 7 would be more robust than others, but none would remain strictly fixed. Such conceptual architecture of the EES would allow explanatory schemes of multilevel causation (sensu Martínez and Esposito 2014), pertinent to the undeniable ontological complexity of biological processes (e.g., morphogenesis) that involve systemic properties across several levels of organization.

In the current state of affairs, whereas portrayed as a big change (see the ‘Yes, urgently’ standpoint in Laland et al. 2014) or as a more nuanced pluralistic alternative framework that hinders the hegemony of the ‘traditional view’ (see Laland et al. 2015), the EES is beginning to outline its structure with a representation not as tidy as a single ‘theory’, but with a much more complex picture bearing resemblance to a diffuse net (Fig. 2). The framework of the EES emphasizes the role of constructive processes in development and evolution, a broader conception of transgenerational inheritance that encompasses many forms of non-genetic variation, and reciprocal representations of causation (Laland et al. 2015). Laland et al. (2015) grant that the impetus for an EES is “undoubtedly complex and multifaceted” (p. 3); nevertheless, they deemed convenient to concentrate their arguments about the incipient structure, assumptions and predictions of the EES on insights derived mainly from four research areas with convergent themes: in their own usage, “developmental plasticity”, “inclusive inheritance”, “niche construction”, and “evolutionary developmental biology” (hence leaving out of the account some important subjects, such as physiology, that had been already discussed under extended evolutionary schemes, see Noble et al. 2014).

Fig. 2
figure 2

The recently stated ‘structure’ of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis, redrawn and modified from Laland et al. (2015), maintaining the concepts and solid/dotted arrows portrayed there, with indication of the interacting ‘processes’ that generate novel variants (e.g., genetic change, developmental processes), bias selection (i.e., niche construction and developmental bias), modify the frequency of heritable variation (i.e., evolutionary forces acting in a population genetics context) and contribute to inclusive transgenerational inheritance (a broadened conception that includes genetic, epigenetic, ecological and cultural inheritance). Concepts shown in red are those emphasized and advocated by the EES, but subsumed, disregarded or deemed negligible by more traditional perspectives. In their original diagram, concepts here written in bold, in our opinion exhibited ambiguous meanings produced by confusions or not sufficiently explicit distinctions between epistemic units and the ontology of natural processes. The peach-colored rectangle demarcates the boundaries of a population of developing organisms. The blue rectangle encompasses processes that generate novel variants; the green rectangle encompasses processes that bias selection; the yellowish rectangle encompasses processes that modify the frequency of heritable variation. Finally, the gray rectangle encompasses processes that contribute to inclusive transgenerational inheritance (color figure online)

There is no question that the paper by Laland et al. (2015) was a commendable first effort to construct a coherent structure for the EES, since one of the main criticisms it had received by then from multiple camps is that the notion of an ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis’ is just a grandiloquent label with an unfathomable common theoretical thread, besides fighting the straw-man of gene-centrism (on these points, see the criticism of Pievani 2016a). Notwithstanding the importance of their meaningful effort, we have detected some misunderstandings that arise from their ambiguous usage of ‘structure’, a tricky philosophical term. The challenges to the SET accentuated by the EES refer to “how evolutionary theory is structured and not simply whether more content must be included” (Love 2017; p. 161). Thorough analyses of the epistemological aspects of science involve making a distinction between the ‘structure’ and ‘content’ of theories and conceptual frameworks. Considerations about the structure of theories, for instance, pertain to the nature of scientific theories themselves (Love 2010) and to questions such as: How is knowledge organized within a circumscribed domain called ‘theory X’? Does the organization of knowledge of a particular theory resemble other scientific theories? In which ways is different or similar? What are the contours of a scientific theory? Should we organize the content of theories following certain epistemic ground rules? (see Love 2017). For philosophers of science, three families of perspectives on the structure of scientific theories are operative (Winther 2015a): the syntactic view (in which theories are conceived as axiomatized collections of sentences, i.e., syntactic logical reconstructions), the semantic view (where theories are conceived as collections of nonlinguistic models open to semantically meaningful mathematical modeling), and the pragmatic view (according to which theories are conceived as amorphous and complex entities closely tied to function and context, consisting variably of sentences, models, exemplars, problems, standards, skills, practices and tendencies). Regardless of the philosophical standpoint, the issue we want to highlight is that the content of scientific theories gets organized by scientists and philosophers in epistemic units (e.g., models, concepts, exemplars, explanations, problems, practices) that relate to each other in defined ways, thereby delineating a structure.Footnote 8 The purported ‘structure’ of the EES in Laland et al. (2015) depicts the relations between classic Neo-Darwinian evolutionary causes (e.g., natural selection, genetic drift) and several additional classes of processes that are newly recognized evolutionary causes (including those that generate novel variation, bias selection and contribute to inheritance), without making explicit how the content (i.e., processes important for biological evolution) should be organized in related epistemic units. For a plural conceptual framework such as the EES, the ambiguity of Laland and collaborators’ characterization of its ‘structure’ lies in its uncertainty regarding the organizational representation of (the relevant) evolutionary processes—i.e., if they are depicted/contained in models, concepts, theories, explanations and/or other epistemic units connected in defined manners. Thematically expanding an evolutionary framework by means of recognizing several additional classes of related evolutionary processes does not suffice to understand the meaningful changes these new components may bring to its conceptual architectureFootnote 9: the clarification of how knowledge about the processes of evolution is organized into distinct and connected epistemic units (i.e., how content is structured) is needed. We show that in Fig. 3 by projecting in two separate but coordinate planes the recently stated ‘structure’ of the EES (based on Laland et al. 2015). To the right, one plane that accommodates concepts that refer to evolutionary relevant processes (i.e., evolutionary causes of phenotypic diversity); to the left, a non-historicized space of contemporary subdisciplines and evolutionary theoriesFootnote 10: models that have explored or have been proposed to explain some of the processes portrayed in the other plane (i.e., the purported ‘core concepts’ of the EES). The clarification of the structure of the EES would require further elaboration of how exactly the study and explanation of evolutionary processes (from natural selection to niche construction and developmental bias) is getting organized into distinct epistemic units and how they relate to each other (i.e., what is the current topology of the structural network). In Fig. 3, the structure of the EES is currently missing but would emerge at the interface of the two planes. Our preliminary analysis of Laland et al. (2015) hints at an emerging conceptual architecture of the EES which resembles a diffuse network (or maybe more than one network) of multiple epistemic units derived from different biological subdisciplines and evolutionary theories/models in complex and pluralistic dialogue, sharing epistemic goals.

Fig. 3
figure 3

The recently stated ‘structure’ of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis, based on Laland et al. (2015), projected with two separate but coordinate planes: to the right, a plane that accommodates concepts that refer to evolutionary relevant natural processes (reproduced from Fig. 2; ‘Plane 1’); to the left, a non-historicized space of contemporary subdisciplines/evolutionary theories that have explored or tried to explain some of the concepts depicted in the other plane (i.e., the purported core concepts of the EES; ‘Plane 2’). The colored rectangles, with the same color code used in Fig. 2, chart correspondences between the two planes: the four kinds of processes depicted in the right plane have been addressed by different, often interacting, subdisciplines/evolutionary theories. Currently, the structure of the EES is missing but would emerge at the interface of the two planes. SET standard evolutionary theory, Evo-Devo evolutionary developmental biology, Eco-Evo-Devo ecological evolutionary developmental biology, NCT niche construction theory, E4D evolution in four dimensions (color figure online)

It should be stressed that the scientific subdisciplines and models [‘Evo-Devo’; ‘developmental plasticity’ (DP)] and evolutionary theories [(‘Niche Construction Theory (NCT); ‘Evolution in 4 Dimensions’ (E4D); ‘Standard Evolutionary Theory’ (SET)] at play are not represented unabridged: several elements of most of them are missing from the conceptual architecture of the EES (see Laland et al. 2015). To give some examples: interpretative mutations (sensu Jablonka and Lamb 2014) are not mentioned; construction chains, important for depicting causal influences in NCT (see Laland and O’Brien 2012), are not formally integrated into the working framework of the EESFootnote 11; epistasis and extinction (important for the defenders of the SET) are being overlooked (see the ‘No, All is Well’ stance in Laland et al. 2014). This could be a reflection of what Ingo Brigandt has seen as a key component of explanatory integration: “solving a complex problem [an epistemic goal] need not require the stable synthesis of different biological fields or the development of genuine interfield theories, as smaller epistemic units [concepts, explanations, methods] from traditional disciplines can be related solely for the purposes of a specific problem” (Brigandt 2010; text inside brackets added). The next section of this article deals with what epistemic units (sensu Brigandt’s epistemology of explanatory integration) of Evo-Devo are present or still missing from the emerging architecture of the EES.

How Evo-Devo and the EES are formally related? What key themes of Evo-Devo are not (yet) formally integrated into the conceptual foundations of the EES?

In the same way we should be wary of the doubtful characterizations that regard the MS as a single comprehensive scientific theory, we should remain skeptical of the claims that depict present Evo-Devo as a single unified theory (see Nuño de la Rosa 2014 for a brief analysis). Moreover, in recent times, the field has suffered a vertiginous expansion with the incorporation of conceptual and technical tools from many subdisciplines, including genomics, ecological and quantitative genetics, the study of developmental plasticity, ecology, paleontology, cell and systems biology, theoretical biology, behavioral sciences, population genetics and a large etcetera (Abouheif and Sears 2015; a trend originally identified by Müller 2007a). As a consequence, the boundaries of evolutionary developmental biology are becoming blurred and harder to demarcate, and so its goals and questions. This is one of the reasons why it is not at all clear how Evo-Devo should be formally integrated into the current evolutionary synthesisFootnote 12 or into the pluralistic EES.Footnote 13 Of the different calls to ‘extend’ the MS that have appeared in recent years, the presence of Evo-Devo (with varying degrees) is, probably, the commonest constituent of all (e.g., Pigliucci 2007; Müller 2007b, 2014; Carroll 2008; Weber 2011), with a shared need to explain the nature and origin of organic form (Love 2017). Despite its epistemic uncertainties, Evo-Devo has achieved a great degree of maturity and recently has been portrayed as a ‘trading zone’ (sensu Peter Galison) due to the complex co-existence of a “variety of disciplines, styles, and paradigms negotiating heavily with one another” (Winther 2015b; p. 459). Given the relentless ‘coming of age’ of the discipline, the time is right to start posing questions about its formal relationships to the EES: How much of Evo-Devo is actually present (integrated or floating isolated) in the current characterizations (i.e., Laland et al. 2015) of the EES? Is it true that “Evo-Devo shapes the Extended Synthesis”? (as claimed in the title of Müller 2014). How the included key themes and epistemic units of Evo-Devo are contributing to shape and alter the trajectories of that nascent framework? Which key themes and epistemic units are foreshadowed or plainly absent? How international practicing scientists of the burgeoning Evo-Devo community are using (or abstaining to use) the framework of the EES in the design of experiments and/or in the interpretation of empirical data?

Not long ago, Gerd Müller remarked that it is still early to grasp the precise appearance of the EES, but it will surely include “an account of the evolution of novelty and complexity, and the dominance of the variation-in-populations approach will recede. Such change entails significant shifts in theory structure, accounting—among other factors—for the dynamics of development, multiple levels of selection, different forms of inheritance, and reciprocity between environment and organismal activity” (Müller 2014; p. 121). Laland et al. (2015) asserted clearly the importance of developmental constructive processes in evolution, and it has been said before that one of the critical aims of the EES is to identify and explain the causal forces of developmental mechanisms that have an essential role in the evolution of organic form (Pigliucci and Müller 2010b; Martínez and Esposito 2014). Just by looking at the pronouncements in the selected references above, one may argue that Evo-Devo’s most simple and fundamental tenet (i.e., knowledge of development is mandatory to fully understand evolutionary processes; stated in Hall 1992; Wagner 2000), is undeniably present in the current state of the EES. But does this mean that the notion of ‘constructive development’ (CD; sensu Laland et al. 2015) is one of the main contributions of Evo-Devo to the EES? We regard that view as inaccurate and partial. Several elements are encapsulated in the notion of CD: non-programmed ontogenies that co-construct its own developmental trajectories (internal and external states) by means of plastically responding to, integrating and shaping environmental cues with causal parity and reciprocal causation. Furthermore, for Laland et al. (2015; p. 6), “the developing organism cannot be reduced to separable components, one of which (e.g., the genome) exerts exclusive control over the other (e.g., the phenotype). Rather, causation also flows back from ‘higher’ (i.e., more complex) levels of organismal organization to the genes (e.g., tissue-specific regulation of gene expression).” CD does not a assume a bijective function (i.e., a one-to-one correspondence) between genotype and phenotype, nor grants causal privilege and programmatic jurisdiction to genes driving individual development; instead, the developmental system is viewed as responding flexibly and creatively to internal and external inputs, through condition-dependent gene expression, and through physical properties of cells and tissues and ‘exploratory behaviors’ of several systems. To say it with their adagio: “Organisms are not built from genetic ‘instructions’ alone, but rather self-assemble using a broad variety of inter-dependent resources” (Laland et al. 2015; p. 6). Taking those views into account,Footnote 14 we argue that the notion of (constructive) development (as used by Laland et al. 2015) cannot be derived entirely from Evo-Devo; it stems from many sources, including developmental systems theory (Oyama 1986), studies of cognition and behavior (see Gottlieb 1992; Oyama et al. 2001), developmental plasticityFootnote 15 (see West-Eberhard 2003) and, of course, evolutionary developmental biology. The preceding statement gains more ground when we recognize that the very notion of ‘development’ is contentious for developmental biology and Evo-Devo (see Minelli and Pradeu 2014). We therefore think that the concept of CD (crucial for Laland et al. 2015) is not the same notion of ‘development’ most Evo-Devo practitioners and developmental biologists have in mind (they usually harbor a multiplicity of heterogeneous concepts and operational definitions of development, if one at all; see Pradeu et al. 2016). Not many evodevoists conceptualize developing organisms as hierarchical systems (in which different levels of organization interact in complex ways) that result from interactive and co-constructive processes and causes (e.g., evolutionary, ecological, developmental), and not mere products of closed or partially open genetic programs; even fewer evodevoists would go as far as to embrace the principle of causal parity. Likewise, it has been stressed that most of contemporary Evo-Devo research is not ‘Devo research’ per se, but is focused predominantly on genetics/genomics and new sophisticated molecular methods, concealing development to the background (Diogo 2016). In the words of Armin Moczek (2012), in current Evo-Devo we see “Too many genes, too little development” (p. 116).

We now focus our attention to other presently incorporated and absent epistemic units of Evo-Devo in the EES. A recurring theme in Laland et al. (2015) is the attention given to the fact that phenotypic variation can be biased by the processes and dynamics of development, channeling the evolution (i.e., increasing the probability of occurrence) of certain functional forms and restricting the possible space of realized forms. Developmental bias (e.g., the nonrandom numbers of meristic elements in the body plans of metazoans) is, by far, the most frequently deployed epistemic unit of Evo-Devo in the discussion of the structure and assumptions of the EES in Laland et al. (2015). Another important key theme for Evo-Devo, facilitated variation (see Kirschner and Gerhart 2005), is used as a conceptual scaffold for explaining the existence of phenotypic variation that is channeled and directed toward functional types (developmental bias): the ‘core processes’ of development concurrently exhibit high robustness and exploratory behaviors that allow them to stabilize and select certain states over others (Laland et al. 2015). Additional key themes of Evo-Devo are marginally mentioned throughout the discussion: for instance, we see the recognition of the existence of modularity in developmental systems and differential coupling and decoupling of phenotypic modules (p. 3); it is mentioned once in the text that phenotypic variation is often the result of alterations in the timing, location, amount or type of gene products brought about by changes in gene regulatory machinery (p. 3; processes that Wallace Arthur has organized under the label ‘developmental repatterning’; see Arthur 2011). The important issue of the evolvability of biological systems, a fundamental topic for Post-Dahlem evolutionary biology (see Wagner 2015), even portrayed by some evodevoists as the proper focus of their discipline (see Hendrikse et al. 2007), appears in the tables and figures of the article, but with only one mention in the corpus of the text (Laland et al. 2015; p. 3). In summary, Evo-Devo ideas discussed in Laland et al. (2015) represent a small fraction of the themes and concepts that, throughout recent history, have been deemed important or fundamental for the discipline. We have prepared a non-exhaustive list of such key themes in Table 1. Of all the terms listed in Table 1, only developmental bias, facilitated variation, and to a considerable lesser extent, modularity and evolvability were used as epistemic units by Laland et al. (2015) to outline the structure and assumptions of the EES.Footnote 16

Table 1 A non-exhaustive list of key themes that have been deemed important or fundamental at some point of the history of the field of Evo-Devo

The potential for including more themes of evolutionary developmental biology and developmental evolution to the EES is enormous. Right now, we see the sum of the epistemic units of Evo-Devo incorporated in the EES as an ‘early ontogenetic stage’ with multiple open developmental trajectories. In a forthcoming, mature EES, for example, epistemic units of Evo-Devo (e.g., evolvability, developmental bias, modularity, but also generative entrenchment, genetic tool-kit, GRN evolution, ChINs, DPMs) could be deployed, alongside epistemic units pertaining to niche construction theory and the views of inclusive inheritance and multilevel causation, to generate integrative explanatory frameworks that tackle macroevolutionary problems such as the evolution and diversification of bilaterian body plans in the early Cambrian (i.e., the so-called ‘Cambrian Explosion’). A good example of what we think are steps in that direction is the recent framework proposed by Laubichler and Renn (2015) to integrate regulatory networks and niche construction, designed to be equally applicable to cases of biological, social and cultural evolution. The semantic field of the concept of CD, as currently used in the EES (Laland et al. 2015), could also be enriched by augmenting the epistemic units derived from Evo-Devo, also following Laubichler and Renn (2015). Finally, proposals for a ‘theory of theory integration’ sensu Laubichler et al. (2018) could be contrasted with our philosophical treatment of explanatory and theoretical integration in the EES—based on the works of Brigandt and Love—to foster additional discussions.

Concluding remarks

We do not interpret the EES as a continuous add-on extension of the SET, where whole new fields, concepts, models and theories are coalescing around a Neo-Darwinian core. Moreover, we do not consider that the EES looks like a bona fide extension at all, as its name implies. It seems that only specific epistemic units, derived from Evo-Devo, niche construction theory, the study of developmental plasticity, Jablonka and Lamb’s ‘evolution in four dimensions’ framework and certain elements of the SET, are being deployed by the proponents of the EES to outline its structure (see Laland et al. 2015). In the alternative image we have presented here, the EES could be articulated around a non-static network (or networks, perhaps) of evolutionary models, practices and representation systems, with edges and nodes that change their position and centrality following the developments of evolutionary biology and allied scientific disciplines. We further propose that the cohesive factor that connects these heterogeneous epistemic units is a set of shared epistemic goals—in particular, an understanding and acceptance of the constructive roles organisms play in shaping their own development and in changing their environments in evolutionary meaningful ways. We are aware that a challenge for the future will be to define with precision what constitutes an epistemic unit of the emerging EES (i.e., which criteria should be used to delimit the nodes of the network), if we want to move beyond philosophical abstraction and start engaging with the actual problems addressed by evolutionary biologists. While that philosophical work is underway, we also want to invite (other) philosophers of science and evolutionary biologists (especially Evo-Devo practitioners) to further suggest how Evo-Devo concepts and themes can be used as epistemic units for the consolidation of a pluralistic and integrative EES. Finally, we want to stress that, beyond worn-out Kuhnian or Lakatosian schemes, different philosophical insights are needed to better understand the interdisciplinary reconfiguration of evolutionary theories that are also opening to different fields of inquiry in the social and human sciences (for instance, a potential dialogue with anthropology; see Ingold 2018; pp. 104–105: see also Fuentes 2016). To better understand the emerging structure and the crucially important evolutionary processes emphasized by the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis, let’s not settle for ready-made philosophical solutions.