Skip to main content
Log in

Plantinga Redux: Is the Scientific Realist Committed to the Rejection of Naturalism?

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While Plantinga has famously argued that acceptance of neo-Darwinian theory commits one to the rejection of naturalism, Plantinga’s argument is vulnerable to an objection developed by Evan Fales. Not only does Fales’ objection undermine Plantinga’s original argument, it establishes a general challenge which any attempt to revitalize Plantinga’s argument must overcome. After briefly laying out the contours of this challenge, we attempt to meet it by arguing that because a purely naturalistic account of our etiology cannot explain the correlation between our preference for simplicity and simplicity’s ability to serve as a veridical method of theory selection, the scientific realist is committed to the rejection of naturalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many thanks to Evan Fales for helping us see this concern.

References

  • Aquinas, T. (1945). Basic writings of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. A.C. Pegis. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2007). Occam’s razor in science: A case study from biogeography. Biology and Philosophy, 22(2), 193–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (1994). Posterior analytics: Translated with a commentary (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beilby, J. (1997). Is evolutionary naturalism self-defeating? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 42(2), 69–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., & Vlerick, M. (2014). Natural selection does care about truth. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(1), 65–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. N. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 19(1), 45–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2014). Scientific realism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). E. N. Zalta (Ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/scientific-realism/>. Accessed 27 Nov 2018.

  • Churchland, P. (1985). The ontological status of observables: In Praise of the Superempirical Virtues. In P. M. Churchland & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism, (with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doppelt, G. (2014). Best theory scientific realism. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 4(2), 271–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2010). The epistemological challenge to metanormative realism: How best to understand it, and how to cope with it. Philosophical Studies, 148(3), 413–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1984). The principle of parsimony and some applications in psychology. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 5, 119–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough, S. H., & Houston, K. (2004). A metabolic measure of mental effort. Biological Psychology, 66(2), 177–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. (1996). Plantinga’s case against naturalistic epistemology. Philosophy of Science, 63, 432–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein, J. (1996). Inferring phylogenies from protein sequences by parsimony, distance, and likelihood methods. Methods in Enzymology, 266, 418–427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B., & Sober, E. (1998). Plantinga’s probability arguments against evolutionary naturalism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79(2), 115–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horton, R. (1967). African traditional thought and Western science. Part I. From tradition to science. Africa: Journal of the International African Institute, 37(1), 50–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, A. (2013). Simplicity, in mathematics and in art. Notices of the AMS, 60(7), 922.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, B. C., Little, A. C., Penton-Voak, I. S., Tiddeman, B. P., Burt, D. M., & Perrett, D. I. (2001). Facial symmetry and judgements of apparent health: Support for a “good genes” explanation of the attractiveness–symmetry relationship. Evolution and Human Behavior, 22(6), 417–429.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45(1), 103–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2012). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, S. (2011). Naturalism, evolution and true belief. Analysis, 72(1), 41–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2003). Inference to the best explanation. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. & Mallon, R. (2010). The evolution of morality. In J. M. Doris & F. Cushman (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook (pp. 4–46). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martens, R. (2009). Harmony and simplicity: Aesthetic virtues and the rise of testability. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 40(3), 258–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masuda, T., Gonzalez, R., Kwan, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (2008). Culture and aesthetic preference: Comparing the attention to context of East Asians and Americans. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(9), 1260–1275.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. C., Gruetter, R., Sonnewald, U., Waagepetersen, H. S., & Schousboe, A. (2005). Energy metabolism of the brain. In G. Siegel, R. W. Albers, S. Brady, & D. Price (Eds.), Basic neurochemistry: molecular, cellular and medical aspects, 7th ed. (pp. 531–558). Cambridge: Elselvier Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1997). Quantitative Parsimony. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(3), 329–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2000). Nature is the realisation of the simplest conceivable mathematical ideas’: Einstein and the canon of mathematical simplicity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 31(2), 135–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palter, R. (1970). An approach to the history of early astronomy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 1(2), 93–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2011). Where the conflict really lies: Science, religion, and naturalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riesch, H. (2010). Simple or simplistic? Scientists’ views on Occam’s razor. Theoria. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 25(1), 75–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, J. W. (1994). Is Naturalism Irrational? Faith and Philosophy 11(2), 255–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosfort, R. (2013). Folk physics. In Encyclopedia of sciences and religions (pp. 863–863). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudner, R. (1961). An introduction to simplicity. Philosophy of Science, 28, 109–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. T. (2007). Living in harmony: Nominalism and the explanationist argument for realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(1), 19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spade, P.V., Panaccio, C. (2016). William of Ockham. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/ockham/>. Accessed 27 Nov 2018.

  • Stanford, K. (2016). Underdetermination of scientific theory. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). E. N. Zalta (Ed.), forthcoming URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/scientific-underdetermination/>. Accessed 27 Nov 2018.

  • Stephens, C. L. (2001). When is it selectively advantageous to have true beliefs? Sandwiching the better safe than sorry argument. Philosophical Studies, 105(2), 161–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C., Churchland, P. M., & Hooker, C. A. (1985). Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, J. S. (1969). Chinese language and Chinese thought. Philosophy East and West, 19(4), 423–434.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Abraham Graber.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Graber, A., Golemon, L. Plantinga Redux: Is the Scientific Realist Committed to the Rejection of Naturalism?. SOPHIA 59, 395–412 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-018-0695-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-018-0695-0

Keywords

Navigation