Advertisement

Morphology

, Volume 28, Issue 2, pp 187–217 | Cite as

Aspect and modality in the interpretation of deverbal -er nominals in English

Article

Abstract

This article presents a corpus study of over 16,000 tokens of -er nominalizations on 62 verbal bases that were extracted from the Corpus of Contemporary American English and the British National Corpus. We show that an individual -er nominal can often be given a range of modal and aspectual readings and that a number of factors influence the availability of different readings for -er nominals, including verb type, syntactic context (verb tenses, adverbs), and encyclopedic information. On the basis of these data, we argue, contra Cohen (2016), that the core meaning of the affix -er (as in writer, printer, etc.) cannot be that of a dynamic modal. We show that neither Cohen’s (2016) analysis nor syntactic analyses such as that of Alexiadou and Schäfer (2010) can account for the range of readings we find. We conclude by sketching one possible analysis in terms of the Lexical Semantic Framework of Lieber (2004, 2016) that postulates underspecified lexical representations of the -er nominals and resolution of underspecification in context.

References

  1. Alexiadou, A., & Schäfer, F. (2010). On the syntax of episodic vs. dispositional -er nominals. In A. Alexiadou & M. Rathert (Eds.), Syntax of nominalizations across languages and frameworks (pp. 9–38). Berlin: de Gruyter. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bauer, L., Lieber, R., & Plag, I. (2013). The Oxford reference guide to English morphology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Booij, G. (1986). Form and meaning in morphology: The case of Dutch ‘agent’ nouns. Linguistics, 24, 503–517. Google Scholar
  4. Borer, H. (2013). Taking form. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  5. Borghini, A., & Williams, N. E. (2008). A dispositional theory of possibility. Dialectica, 62, 21–41. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brandtner, R., & von Heusinger, K. (2010). Nominalization in context—Conflicting readings and predicate transfer. In M. Rathert & A. Alexiadou (Eds.), The semantics of nominalizations across languages and frameworks (pp. 25–49). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cohen, A. (2016). A semantic explanation for the external argument generalization. Morphology, 26, 91–103. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Heyvaert, L. (2003). A cognitive-functional approach to nominalization in English. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Heyvaert, L. (2010). A cognitive-functional perspective on deverbal nominalization in English: Descriptive findings and theoretical ramifications. In M. Rathert & A. Alexiadou (Eds.), The semantics of nominalizations across languages and frameworks (pp. 51–81). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Huddleston, R., & Pullum, G. (2002). The Cambridge grammar of English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
  11. Kratzer, A. (1977). What ‘must’ and ‘can’ must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1(3), 337–355. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Levin, B. (1993). English verb class and alternations: a preliminary investigation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Google Scholar
  13. Levin, B., & Rappaport Hovav, M. (1988). Non-event -er nominals: A probe into argument structure. Linguistics, 26, 1067–1083. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Levin, B., & Rappaport Hovav, M. (1995). Unaccusativity. Cambridge: MIT Press. Google Scholar
  15. Lieber, R. (2004). Morphology and lexical semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lieber, R. (2016). English nouns: The ecology of nominalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Löbner, S. (2013). Understanding semantics (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge. Google Scholar
  18. Palmer, F. (1990). Modality and the English Modals (2nd ed.). London: Longman. Google Scholar
  19. Palmer, F. (2003). Modality in English. In R. Facchinetti, M. Krug, & F. Palmer (Eds.), Modality in contemporary English (pp. 1–17). Berlin: Mouton. Google Scholar
  20. Papafragou, A. (1998). Inference and word meaning: The case of modal auxiliaries. Lingua, 105(1–2), 1–47. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Plag, I., Andreou M., & Kawaletz L. (2017). A frame-semantic approach to polysemy in affixation. In O. Bonami, G. Boyé, G. Dal, H. Giraudo, F. Namer (Eds.) The lexeme in descriptive and theoretical morphology. Berlin: Language Science Press. Google Scholar
  22. Rappaport Hovav, M., & Levin, B. (1992). -ER nominals: Implications for the theory of argument structure. In T. Stowell & E. Wehrli (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, vol. XXVI: syntax and the lexicon (pp. 127–153). New York: Academic Press. Google Scholar
  23. Roeper, T. (1987). Implicit arguments and the head-complement relation. Linguistic Inquiry, 18, 267–310. Google Scholar
  24. Ryder, M. (1999). Bankers and blue-chippers: an account of -er formations in present-day English. English Language and Linguistics, 3, 269–297. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Salkie, R., Busuttil, P., & Auwera, J. (Eds.) (2009). Modality in English: Theory and description. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. Google Scholar
  26. van Hout, A., & Roeper, T. (1998). Events and aspectual structure in derivational morphology. In H. Harley (Ed.), MITWPL: Vol. 32. Papers from the UPenn/MIT roundtable on argument structure and aspect (pp. 175–200). Cambridge: MIT. Google Scholar
  27. Vetter, B. (2013). Can’ without possible worlds: semantics for anti-humeans. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(16), 1–27. Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of New HampshireDurhamUSA
  2. 2.Heinrich Heine UniversityDüsseldorfGermany

Personalised recommendations