Skip to main content
Log in

Camus’s Absurd and the Argument against Suicide

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are striking differences between Camus’s early and late philosophical essays, but Camus often claimed that his works were part of one consistent project. This paper argues that, although Camus had a significant change in his views on the consequences of the absurd, throughout his life he also had a common concern with the relation of the absurd to morality. Showing this requires us to clarify what Camus meant by the “absurd,” and identify at least three different uses of the term by Camus: lacking a purpose; lacking an explanation; and a tension between purpose and purposelessness. Clarifying the meaning of “absurd” allows one to show that Camus’s late argument against suicide, often dismissed as inadequate, is valid. This also illustrates the consistency of his concerns over time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some scholars have put this experience of the absurd at the center of their accounts. David Carroll (2007) argues that for Camus the feeling of the experience of the absurd signifies facts about the absurd that cannot be captured in theory.

  2. Cruikshank (1960: 45) quotes Sartre as having this view also: “Camus’s philosophy is a philosophy of the absurd. For him the absurd arises from the relation between man and the world, between man’s rational demands and the world’s irrationality.” (I have been unable to find the original quote.)

  3. Camus does recommend a certain form of skepticism as a personal virtue, but this is a different matter. In The Rebel he is concerned that we should not use our political theories to justify violence, and argues that we should be skeptical about their accuracy. A valuable discussion of this is to be found in Sharpe (2015). Camus is also concerned that we should be skeptical about political theories. But this skepticism is actually derivable from the notion of teleological absurdity, since what concerned Camus was that the prophecies of Marx or Hegel were used as consequentialist justifications for violence. Here again, Camus is rejecting some kinds of teleological explanations and not causal explanations.

  4. The exceptions are rare, and include things like when the organism breaks down, such as through illness. Thus, we could answer the question, “Why isn’t Tom here?” with something like, “Because he did not want to come.” Which is an explanation in terms of his purposes. An example of the (more rare) causal explanation would be something like: “Because he has the flu.”

  5. See also (2004:205).

  6. A strikingly similar account of the affront of suffering is given by Nietzshe in his third Untimely Meditation (1997 [1874]: 157).

  7. Also, some scholars have asserted that Camus’s abilities as a philosopher were not worthy of serious consideration. The view is expressed strongly, for example, by Beauvoir: “Camus had a very simplistic mind, and he took extremely simplistic views on politics, ethics and philosophy. He wrote well, but he was not a profound man. The difference between him and Sartre is that Sartre was a true philosopher and Camus was a pure journalist, a journalist who was also a bit of a writer…. Nobody in France today reads anything he wrote. It was all too facile, too obvious.” (Bair, 1991: 290). Even literary critics like Susan Sontag have been dismissive (which is remarkable when we note how literary critics tend to celebrate even the most fanciful of theories): “Starting from the premises of a popular nihilism, [Camus] moves the reader—solely by the power of his own tranquil voice and tone—to humanist and humanitarian conclusions in no way entailed by his premises. This illogical leaping of the abyss to nihilism is the gift for which readers are grateful to Camus” (1963).

  8. I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for Philosophia for many helpful comments.

References

  • Aristotle (2000). Nicomachean ethics. Translated by Roger Crisp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bair, D. (1991). Simone de Beauvoir: A biography. New York: Touchstone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beauvoir, Simone (1948 [1947]). The ethics of ambiguity. Translated by Bernard Frechtman. New Jersey: Citadel Press.

  • Camus, Albert (1955 [1942]). The myth of Sisyphus. Translated by Justin O’Brian. New York: Vintage.

  • Camus, Albert (1956 [1951]). The rebel. Translated by Anthony Bower. New York: Vintage Books.

  • Camus, Albert (1958). Caligula. In Albert Camus: Caligula and three other plays, translated by Stuart Gilbert: 1–74. New York: Vintage.

  • Camus, Albert (1960 [1944]). Fourth letter to a German friend. In Resistance, rebellion, and death, translated by Justin O’Brien: 26–32. New York: Knopf.

  • Camus, Albert (1972 [1947]). The plague. Translated by Stuart Gilbert. New York: Vintage.

  • Camus, Albert (2004). In defense of the rebel. In Sartre and Camus: A historic confrontation, edited and translated by David Sprintzen and Adrian van den Hoven: 205–221. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.

  • Camus, Albert (2012 [1945]) No, I am not an existentialist. In Lyrical and critical essays, edited by Philip Thody and translated by Ellen Kennedy: 345–349. New York: Vintage.

  • Carroll, D. (2007). Rethinking the absurd: Le Mythe de Sisyphe. In E. Hughes (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Camus (pp. 53–66). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cruickshank, J. (1960). Albert Camus and the literature of revolt. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, John (2008). Albert Camus: From the absurd to revolt. Taylor and Francis.

  • Heidegger, Martin (1962 [1927]) Being and time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Hochberg, H. (1965). Albert Camus and the Ethic of Absurdity. Ethics, 75, 87–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich (1997 [1874]) Schopenhauer as educator. In Untimely meditation, edited by Daniel Braezeale and translated by R. J. Hollingdale: 127–194. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Pölzler, T. (2018). Camus’ feeling of the absurd. Journal of Value Inquiry, 52, 477–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sagi, Avi (2002) Albert Camus and the philosophy of the absurd. Translated by Batya Stein. New York: Rodopi (Value Inquiry Book Series).

  • Scott, N. (1969). Albert Camus. New York: Hilary House Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe, M. (2015). On a neglected argument in French philosophy: Sceptical humanism in Montaigne, Voltaire and Camus. Critical Horizons, 16(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sontag, Susan (1963). The ideal husband (review of notebooks, 1935–1942, by Albert Camus). New York Review of Books, September 26 issue.

  • Wollheim, R. (1953). The political philosophy of existentialism. The Cambridge Journal, VII(1), 3–19.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Craig DeLancey.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

DeLancey, C. Camus’s Absurd and the Argument against Suicide. Philosophia 49, 1953–1971 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00333-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00333-7

Keywords

Navigation