Skip to main content
Log in

For-Me-Ness, For-Us-Ness, and the We-Relationship

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article investigates the relationship between for-me-ness and sociality. I start by pointing out some ambiguities in claims pursued by critics that have recently pressed on the relationship between the two notions. I next articulate a question concerning for-me-ness and sociality that builds on the idea that, occasionally at least, there is something it is like ‘for us’ to have an experience. This idea has been explored in recent literature on shared experiences and collective intentionality, and it gestures towards the question of the extent to which some social interactions make a difference in the phenomenal character of their participants’ experiences. Finally, I present a construal of for-us-ness that complements the received understanding of for-me-ness, by drawing on Alfred Schutz’ concept of the we-relationship, and on the idea of second-personal awareness, i.e. awareness of a ‘you’ (as distinguished from awareness of a ‘she’ or ‘he’). The current proposal provides a suitable account of some basic forms of phenomenally manifest social connectedness, in a way that is cognitively undemanding and without incurring the costs of a sui generis plural pre-reflective self-awareness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For some recent discussions, see (Guillot 2017; Garfield 2016; Schear 2009; Dainton 2016; Zahavi 2019; Zahavi and Kriegel 2016; Kriegel 2005, 2011a).

  2. Challenging the idea that “experiences in-themselves” can be characterized “in terms of feelings of ‘mineness’ or ‘first-personal giveness’” without appeal to intersubjectively acquired concepts, Hutto and Ilundáin-Agurruza ask: “what entitles us to employ these sorts of characterization in describing the felt character of such experiences to experiencers who lack the ability to make such conceptual distinctions?” (forthcoming, p. 19) This line of questioning seems to leave unexplained, though, wat would entitle us to talk of experiencers in the first place.

  3. Although some of these critics discuss minimal selfhood and not for-me-ness, I will make in the following the important assumption that the two notions are co-referential (Zahavi forthcoming, p. 9, 2014, p. 88). I take it that when the critics address the most basic aspects of selfhood and subjectivity, the strongest and most interesting way to understand their claim is as targeting for-me-ness. It is of course an open possibility to deny that the notions of for-me-ness and minimal selfhood capture the same phenomenon. However, a consequence of this denial would be that the aspects of minimal selfhood discussed by the critics would not speak to the idea that for-me-ness is fundamentally determined by social interactions.

  4. The model of a state is understood in this context along the lines of the free energy framework, as a probabilistic and inferential model that is updated according to the incoming information to the system (Friston 2010; Fotopoulou and Tsakiris 2017, p. 7).

  5. Perhaps one possible move to make here, congenial to enactivist and extended approaches to cognition, would be to put pressure on a too strong distinction between causation and constitution (Kirchhoff 2015). However, the pertinence of that denial in the present context would have to be made explicit and substantiated.

  6. For further discussion of recent criticisms to for-me-ness and minimal selfhood that focus on the issue of sociality, see (Zahavi 2010, 2014, p. 85, 2016, 2017; Zahavi and Rochat 2017).

  7. Campbell thinks of the shift in question primarily as a change in the functional role of the experience, insofar as being part of a joint attention relation opens up new action possibilities, but he also acknowledges that joint attention is not exhausted by its functional roles (Campbell 2005, p. 294). A classic example of an action possibility enabled by joint attention is the ‘coordinated attack’ scenario. On one version of it, it involves two subjects, A and B, who are playing a war game displayed on a screen in front of them. A and B are allies and, according to the rules of the game, if they attack the same target, a limited payoff is guaranteed, whereas, if either attacks a target without the other attacking the same target, the outcome is disaster. Campbell remarks that, in an ordinary situation, it is perfectly possible for A and B to attack the same target. Their joint attention to the same target is out in the open for both of them: “[y]ou point and I nod. Straightway we hit the buttons” (Campbell 2011, p. 417). Campbell’s critical point is that no n level of iterative common knowledge is sufficient to rationalize the coordinated attack. He proposes that it is in virtue of being responsive to the three-place experiential relation of joint attention that the co-attenders can be successful in attacking the same target. For a recent discussion of the coordinated attack scenario, see Blomberg (forthcoming).

  8. Most notably, the topic seems to be absent in Kriegel’s rich and detailed treatment (2015).

  9. As far as I can see, the locution ‘for us’ in the context of discussions on phenomenal consciousness was introduced by Schmid, who writes: “In the case of shared feelings—shared grief, worries, and joys—there is a sense in which it is simply not the case that “I can’t really know how you feel,” because my feeling is your feeling, or rather: my feeling isn’t really mine, and yours isn’t yours, but ours. Shared feelings are conscious experiences whose subjective aspect is not singular (“for me”), but plural (“for us”)” (Schmid 2014b, p. 9).

  10. “The father and the mother stand beside the dead body of a beloved child. They feel in common the ‘same’ sorrow, the ‘same’ anguish. It is not that A feels this sorrow and B feels it also, and moreover that they both know they are feeling it. No, it is a feeling-in-common. A’s sorrow is in no way ‘objectual’ for B here, as it is, e.g. for their friend C, who joins them, and commiserates ‘with them’ or ‘upon their sorrow’. On the contrary, they feel it together, in the sense that they feel and experience in common, not only the self-same value-situation, but also the same keenness of emotion in regard to it. The sorrow, as value-content, and the grief, as characterizing the functional relation thereto, are here one and identical”. (Scheler 2008, pp. 12–13, translation modified.)

  11. As Naomi Eilan writes, “[t]here is something utterly simple and basic about the transparency of our minds to each other in the case of joint attention which this whole account [Schiffer’s] misses. The very idea that we have to iterate beliefs ad infinitum in order to capture the phenomenon of mutual awareness only gets going because of an assumption of basic opacity as a starting point” (Eilan 2005, p. 3).

  12. “It is constitutive of the phenomenon [of joint attention] that when it occurs its occurrence is mutually manifest to the co-attenders” (Eilan 2015, p. 1); “when joint attention occurs everything about the fact that both subjects are attending to the same object is out in the open, manifest to both participants” (Eilan 2005, p. 1); “whatever else is true of it, joint attention has an ‘openness’ about it—there’s some sense in which the situation is ‘open’ to both attendees in a case of joint attention” (Campbell 2011, p. 417); “when there is full joint awareness between subjects, there is awareness of full joint awareness” (Peacocke 2005, p. 303); See also (Carpenter and Liebal 2011, p. 160; Schilbach 2015, p. 132; Moll and Meltzoff 2011b, p. 290).

  13. To be fair, Schmid does not discuss mutual awareness of co-presence. I am extrapolating and adapting arguments of his to the case at hand.

  14. One problem is how to account for inter-individual phenomenal differences if sharing involves one token-identical experiential episode. For a criticism of the token-identity view, see Zahavi (in press); León et al. 2017.

  15. Thanks to Dan Zahavi, Anne-Sofie Munk Autzen, Olle Blomberg, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and suggestions.

References

  • Bennett K (2011) Construction area (no hard hat required). Philos Stud 154(1):79–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blomberg O (in press) We-experiences, common knowledge and the mode approach to collective intentionality. J Soc Philos

  • Bruner J (1995) From joint attention to the meeting of minds: an introduction. In: Moore C, Dunham PJ (eds) Joint attention: its origins and role in development. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2005) Joint attention and common knowledge. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2011) An object-dependent perspective on joint attention. In: Seemann A (ed) Joint attention: new developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter M, Liebal K (2011) Joint attention, communication, and knowing together in infancy. In: Seemann A (ed) Joint attention: new developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2000) Phenomenal consciousness. A naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ciaunica A (2016) Basic forms of pre-reflective self-consciousness: a developmental perspective. In: Miguens S, Preyer G, Bravo Morando C (eds) Pre-reflective consciousness: sartre and contemporary philosophy of mind. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciaunica A, Fotopoulou A (2017) The touched self: psychological and philosophical perspectives on proximal intersubjectivity and the self. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (eds) Embodiment, enaction, and culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2016) I—The sense of self. Aristot Soc Suppl 90(1):113–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Haan S (2010) The minimal self is a social self. In: Fuchs T, Sattel H, Henningsen P (eds) The embodied self: dimensions, coherence, and disorders. Schattauer, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Eilan N (2005) Joint attention, communication, and mind. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. OUP, New York

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eilan N (2014) The you turn. Philos Explor 17(3):265–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eilan N (2015) Joint attention and the second person (draft). Retrieved from http://www2.warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/philosophy/people/eilan/jasphum.pdf. Accessed 23 Mar 2018

  • Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) (2005) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fotopoulou A, Tsakiris M (2017) Mentalizing homeostasis: the social origins of interoceptive inference. Neuropsychoanalysis 19(1):3–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston K (2010) The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory. Nat Rev: Neurosci 11:127–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2008) Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Conscious Cogn 17(2):535–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield J (2016) Illusionism and giveness. J Conscious Stud 23(11–12):73–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Guillot M (2017) I me mine: on a confusion concerning the subjective character of experience. Rev Philos Psychol 8:23–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson RP (2002) The cradle of thought. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto D (2008) Articulating and understanding the phenomenological manifesto. Abstracta 10(19):10–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto D, Ilundáin-Agurruza J (forthcoming) Selfless activity and experience: the late emergence of minimal self-awareness. Retrieved from https://www.academia.edu/35544492/Selfless_Activity_and_Experience_The_Late_Emergence_of_Minimal_Self-Awareness. Accessed 23 Mar 2018

  • Kirchhoff M (2015) Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: in search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Phenomenol Res 90(2):320–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2005) Naturalizing subjective character. Phenomenol Res 71(1):23–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2011a) Self-representationalism and the explanatory gap. In: Liu J, Perry J (eds) Consciousness and the self: new essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2011b) Subjective consciousness: a self-representational theory. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2015) The varieties of consciousness. OUP, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (forthcoming) The three circles of consciousness. In: Guillot M, Garcia-Carpintero M (eds) The sense of mineness. OUP, Oxford. Retrieved from https://philpapers.org/archive/KRITTC.pdf. Accessed 23 Mar 2018

  • Krueger J (2012) Seeing mind in action. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 11(2):149–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger J (2016) The affective “We”: self-regulation and shared emotions. In: Szanto T, Moran D (eds) Phenomenology of sociality: discovering the we. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyselo M (2016) The minimal self needs a social update. Philos Psychol 29(7):1057–1065

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • León F (2013) Experiential other-directness: to what does it amount?. Tidsskrift for Medier, Erkendelse og Formidling 1(1):21–38

    Google Scholar 

  • León F, Zahavi D (2016) Phenomenology of experiential sharing: the contribution of Schutz and Walther. In: Salice A, Schmid HB (eds) The phenomenological approach to social reality: history, concepts, problems. Springer, Cham, pp 219–234

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • León F, Szanto T, Zahavi D (2017) Emotional sharing and the extended mind. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1351-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (2001) Purple haze: the puzzle of consciousness. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (2002) Convention: a philosophical study. Blackwell, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Litt T (1926) Individuum und Gemeinschaft. Grundlegung der Kulturphilosophie. B.G. Teubner, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll H, Meltzoff AN (2011a) Joint attention as the fundamental basis of understanding perspectives. In: Seemann A (ed) Joint attention: new developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll H, Meltzoff AN (2011b) Perspective-taking and its foundation in joint attention. In: Roessler J, Lerman H, Eilan N (eds) Perception, causation, and objectivity. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C (2005) Joint attention: its nature, reflexivity, and relation to common knowledge. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz W (2003) Emerging selves: representational foundations of subjectivity. Conscious Cogn 12(4):515–528

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz W (2017) Modeling self on others: an import theory of subjectivity and selfhood. Conscious Cogn 49:347–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe M (2017) Selfhood, schizophrenia, and the interpersonal regulation of experience. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (eds) Embodiment, enaction, and culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy V (2008) How infants know minds. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal DM (2002) Explaining consciousness. In: Chalmers DJ (ed) Philosophy of mind: classical and contemporary readings. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schear JK (2009) Experience and self-consciousness. Philos Stud 144(1):95–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler M (2008) The nature of sympathy. Transaction Publishers, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S (1972) Meaning. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schilbach L (2015) Eye to eye, face to face and brain to brain: novel approaches to study the behavioral dynamics and neural mechanisms of social interactions. Curr Opin Behav Sci 3:130–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schilbach L, Timmermans B, Reddy V, Costall A, Bente G, Schlicht T, Vogeley K (2013) Toward a second-person neuroscience. Behav Brain Sci 36(04):393–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid HB (2005) Wir-Intentionalität: Kritik des ontologischen Individualismus und Rekonstruktion der Gemeinschaft. Alber, Freiburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid HB (2009) Plural action. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid HB (2014a) Plural self-awareness. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 13(1):7–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid HB (2014b) The feeling of being a group. Corporate emotions and collective consciousness. In: von Scheve C, Salmela M (eds) Collective emotions: perspectives from psychology, philosophy, and sociology. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid HB (2015) Collective emotions—phenomenology, ontology, and ideology. What should we learn from Max Scheler’s War Propaganda? Thaumàzein - Rivista di Filosofia 3:103–120. https://doi.org/10.13136/thau.v3i0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A (1962) Collected papers I. The problem of social reality. M. Nijhoff, Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A (1967) Phenomenology of the social world. Northwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A (1970) Collected papers III. Studies in phenomenological philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A (1976) Collected papers II. Studies in social theory. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A, Luckmann T (1973) The structures of the life-world, vol I. Northwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweikard D, Schmid HB (2013) Collective intentionality. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, CSLI, Palo Alto

    Google Scholar 

  • Seemann A (ed) (2011) Joint attention: new developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Spitz R (1977) The first year of life: a psychoanalytic study of normal and deviant development of object relations. International University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Szanto T (2015) Collective emotions, normativity, and empathy: a Steinian account. Hum Stud 38(4):503–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen D (2014) A dynamic theory of shared intention and the phenomenology of joint action. In: Chant SR, Hindriks F, Preyer G (eds) From individual to collective intentionality. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2014) A natural history of human thinking. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen C (1979) Communication and cooperation in early infancy: a description of primary intersubjectivity. In: Bullowa MM (ed) Before speech: the beginning of interpersonal communication. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen C (1998) The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity. In: Bråten S (ed) Intersubjective communication and emotion in early ontogeny. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen C, Hubley P (1978) Secondary intersubjectivity: confidence, confiding and acts of meaning in the first year. In: Lock A (ed) Action, gesture and symbol: the emergence of language. Academic Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick E (2004) Why is connection with others so critical? The formation of dyadic states of consciousness and the expansion of individuals’ states of consciousness: coherence governed selection and the co-creation of meaning out of messy meaning making. In: Nadel J, Muir D (eds) Emotional development: recent research advances. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf P, Sillari G (2014) Common knowledge. In: Zalta EN (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/common-knowledge/

  • Walther G (1923) Zur Ontologie der sozialen Gemeinschaften (mit einem Anhang zur Phänomenologie der sozialen Gemeinschaften). In: Husserl E (ed) Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung VI, pp 1–158

  • Williford K (2015) Representationalisms, subjective character, and self-acquaintance. Theoretical philosophy/MIND group – JGU mainz. Retrieved from http://www.open-mind.net/DOI?isbn=9783958570054. Accessed 23 Mar 2018

  • Ylikoski P (2013) Causal and constitutive explanation compared. Erkenntnis 78(S2):277–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood: investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2010) Reply: … even in the absence of social interaction? In: Fuchs T, Sattel H, Henningsen P (eds) The embodied self: dimensions, coherence, and disorders. Schattauer, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2011) Empathy and direct social perception: a phenomenological proposal. Rev Philos Psychol 2(3):541–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2014) Self and other: exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2015a) Self and other: from pure ego to co-constituted we. Cont Philos Rev 48(2):143–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2015b) You, me, and we: the sharing of emotional experiences. J Conscious Stud 22:84–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2016) Openness versus interdependence: a reply to Kyselo. Philos Psychol 29(7):1066–1067

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2017) Thin, thinner, thinnest: defining the minimal self. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (eds) Embodiment, enaction, and culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2019) Consciousness and (minimal) selfhood: getting clearer on for-me-ness and mineness. In: Kriegel U (ed) The oxford handbook of the philosophy of consciousness. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (in press). Collective intentionality and plural pre-reflective self-awareness. J Soc Philos

  • Zahavi D, Gallagher S (2008) Reply: a phenomenology with legs and brains. Abstracta 4(3):86–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D, Kriegel U (2016) For-me-ness: what it is and what it is not. In: Dahlstrom DO, Elpidorou A, Hopp W (eds) Philosophy of mind and phenomenology: conceptual and empirical approaches. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D, Rochat P (2017) Embodied mentalization and selfhood: commentary on “mentalizing homeostasis: the social origins of interoceptive inference” by Fotopoulou and Tsakiris. Neuropsychoanalysis 19(1):67–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author thanks the Independent Research Fund Denmark for financial support to the project ‘You and We: Second-person Engagement and Collective Intentionality’, DFF—7013-00032).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felipe León.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

León, F. For-Me-Ness, For-Us-Ness, and the We-Relationship. Topoi 39, 547–558 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9556-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9556-2

Keywords

Navigation