Does the normative question about rationality rest on a mistake?
- 141 Downloads
Abstract
Rationality requires that our mental attitudes exhibit specific patterns of coherence. Do we have reason to comply? ’Prichardian Quietists’ regard this question as fundamentally confused: the only reasons to comply with rational requirements are the ones given by the requirements themselves. In this paper, I argue that PQ fails. I proceed by granting that Prichard’s own position, from which PQ draws inspiration, is defensible, while identifying three serious problems with the parallel position about rationality. First, as I argue, PQ is not plausibly combined with either the narrow-scope or the wide-scope formulations of rational requirements. Second, PQ implies that the reasons to comply with rational requirements are reasons of the wrong kind. And finally, PQ lacks a crucial component of its explanation, viz. a plausible theory of what constitutes being rationally required to V.
Keywords
Rational requirements Normativity of rationality Scope H. A. Prichard Reasons of the wrong kindNotes
Acknowledgements
For their very helpful comments on, and discussions of, earlier drafts of this paper, I am extremely grateful to Hagit Benbaji, Dalia Drai, Alex Gregory, David Horst, Naomi Korem, Jonathan Way, Ruth Weintraub, audiences at Cardiff University and the meeting of the European Normativity Network at Humboldt University, and two anonymous referees for this journal.
References
- Black, S., & Tiffany, E. (2007). Introduction: Moral philosophy does not rest on a mistake: Reasons to be moral revisited. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 37(Supplement), 7–40.Google Scholar
- Bratman, M. (1987). Intentions, plans, and practical reason. London: Harvard Univerity Press.Google Scholar
- Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. London: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Broome, J. (2008). Reply to Southwood, Kearns and star, and Cullity. Ethics, 119, 96–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Broome, J. (2005). Does rationality give us reasons? Philosophical Issues, 15, 321–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Broome, J. (2004). Reasons. In R. J. Wallace, M. Smith, S. Scheffler, & P. Pettit (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 28–55). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Broome, J. (1999). Normative requirements. Ratio, 12, 398–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Brunero, J. (2015). Review of Mark Schroeder’s ‘explaining the reasons we share’. Ethics, 126, 238–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Dancy, J. (2014). Harold Arthur Prichard. In Edward N. Zalta (Eds.)The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/prichard/>.
- Dancy, J. (2009). Rationality and Reasons. In S. Robertson (Ed.), Spheres of reason (pp. 93–112). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). Sentiment and value. Ethics, 110, 722–748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Hussain, N. (ms). The requirements of rationality, Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
- Kant, I. (1948). Groundwork of the metaphysic of morals, translated by H. J. Paton (Hutchinson)Google Scholar
- Kavka, G. (1983). The toxin puzzle. Analysis, 43, 33–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kelly, T. (2002). The rationality of belief and some other propositional attitudes. Philosophical Studies, 90, 163–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kolodny, N. (2008). Why be disposed to be coherent? Ethics, 118, 437–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kolodny, N. (2007). How does coherence matter? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107, 229–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational? Mind, 114, 509–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Owens, D. (2000). Reasons without freedom. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Parfit, D. (2001). Rationality and reasons. In D. Egonsson, J. Josefsson, B. Petersson, & T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (Eds.), Exploring practical philosophy: From action to values (pp. 19–39). London: Ashgate.Google Scholar
- Persson, I. (2007). Primary and secondary reasons. In T. Rønnow-Rasmussen, B. Petersson, J. Josefsson, & D. Egonsson (Eds.), Homage à Wlodek: Philosophical papers dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz. Lund: Lund University.Google Scholar
- Pink, T. (1996). The psychology of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Prichard, H. A. (2002). Moral writings. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Ross, J. (2009). How to be a cognitivist about practical reason. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics volume 4 (pp. 243–281). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Schroeder, M. (2010). Value and the right kind of reason. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics, volume 5 (pp. 25–55). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Schroeder, M. (2009). Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons. Philosophical Studies, 43, 223–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Setiya, K. (2007). Cognitivism about instrumental reason. Ethics, 117, 647–673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Shah, N. (2006). A new argument for evidentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 481–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Shah, N. (2008). How action governs intention. Philosophers’ Imprint, 8, 1–19.Google Scholar
- Skorupski, J. (2010). The domain of reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Southwood, N. (2008). Vindicating the normativity of rationality. Ethics, 119, 9–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Way, J. (2012a). Explaining the instrumental principle. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 487–506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Way, J. (2012b). Transmission and the wrong kind of reason. Ethics, 122, 489–515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar