Skip to main content
Log in

Should Liberal States Subsidize Religious Schooling?

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many liberals and secularists believe that religious schooling should not be publicly funded or that it should simply be banned. Challenging those views, I claim that although liberal states may refuse to fund and may even ban certain illiberal separate religious schools, it is impermissible, for distinctively liberal reasons, to completely ban publicly funded religious schooling. I will however argue that providing religious instruction within common public schools is more desirable than having separate religious schools. I argue that providing religious instruction within common public schools (for all religious options with enough adherents) is a better way to balance the educational interests of parents, children and society than (1) banning religious schooling altogether; (2) authorizing it but refusing to fund it; (3) or having publicly funded separate religious schools.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I thus follow a well-established distinction between religious instruction and religious education where the former aims at promoting a particular faith whereas later takes a sociological approach to religion and aims at familiarizing students with the phenomenon of religious belief. Many societies have felt the need to introduce pupils to the fact of religious pluralism and to offer courses of religious education (not instruction) with titles such as “Religions of the world”, “Religious culture” or “Science of religions”.

  2. Parental partiality can mean two things. It can refer to the desires and attempts of parents to confer positional or competitive advantages to their children (for instance, paying for a better school) or it can refer to the desires and attempts of parents in trying to influence the development of the character, values and beliefs of their children. See Brighouse and Swift (2014). I am here only concerned with the second meaning of “parental partiality”.

  3. Brighouse and Swift’s main concern, however, is not to defend public funds for religious private schools. They rather aim at explaining why parents need not be absolutely impartial and neutral about the ways of life and values that the education they provide to their children promotes. For a defence of the opposite position regarding parental partiality, see Clayton (2006, 2012).

  4. Brighouse and Swift also provide another argument for parental partiality. This second argument derives parental partiality from the right of children to be raised in families, to be raised by a loving parent or parents. They claim that parents’ legitimate educational partiality is both derivative from parents’ interests and from children’s interests (2006, pp. 84–89, 2014, pp. 149–174).

  5. For other versions of arguments for legitimate parental authority pointing in different directions, see Burtt (1994, 1996), Macleod (1997), Zwarthoed (2015), Cormier (2018) and Dumitru (2018).

  6. Wisconsin vYoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1972).

  7. For Rawls, primary goods are: “things that every rational man is presumed to want. These goods normally have a use whatever a person’s rational plan of life” (1999a, b, p. 54).

  8. Indeed, the argument that I develop also implies that that parents’ educational choices should not only extent to religious schooling but also to forms of schooling that emphasize secular humanist teachings, sports or arts. It relies on the view that religion should not be treated as being uniquely special in the realm of schooling. I support this claim in “Equal Opportunity for Parental Partiality” section. Laborde (2017) offers the most sophisticated defense of the view that religion should not be treated as special vis-à-vis other substantive commitments.

  9. I follow the usual distinction between neutrality of aim, which prohibits the state from adopting policies aiming at making some conception of the good life more or less successful, neutrality of effects, which prohibits the state from adopting policies that have the effect of making some conception of the good more or less successful, and neutrality of justification, which prohibits the state from justifying its policies on the basis that some conception of the good is intrinsically superior or inferior to others (Patten 2014, pp. 111–114). Patten ads a fourth conception of neutrality: neutrality of treatment, which prohibits the state from being more accommodating of some conceptions of the good than they are for others (2014, p. 115). In “Equal Opportunity for Parental Partiality” section, I explain that my argument is compatible with one of the three strategies for achieving neutrality of treatment discussed by Patten.

  10. A court may nonetheless establish that it is too costly for an employer to grant prayer pauses or room for prayers on a daily basis to all believers demanding it. Establishing that a religious accommodation is too costly for an employer is a legitimate reason to deny the accommodation compatible with justificatory neutrality. Claiming that praying at a specific moment of the day or week is not necessary to fulfil one’s religious duties is entirely different from the point of view of neutrality. See for instance Maclure and Taylor (2010, pp. 100–104).

  11. It could be difficult to assess whether a specific school is moderate or not. How should we regard a school that teaches that contraception is a sin and that God created the world six thousand years ago? One important criteria for moderate religious schooling is that secular teachings must be kept separate and autonomous from religious doctrines. For instance, religious doctrines must not pervade courses of biology, ethics or history and they must not be presented as biological, ethical or historical truths. In such moderate schools, religious teachings are offered in addition to basic instruction, not as a substitute for it.

  12. It is important to note that those authors do not develop a principled objection to separate (ethnic or religious) schools. Kymlicka is inclined to believe that common schools perform better than separate schools to promote the integration of children from ethnoreligious immigrant minorities. Callan claims that common schools provide better conditions for the establishment of deliberative settings which fulfil the dialogical task of schooling. The idea is not that separate schools are necessarily unjust (although they are when they treat children as ethical servants), but that they are less likely to advance the legitimate aim of creating reasonable citizens equipped with the tools required to understand and respond respectfully to the claims made by citizens with whom they profoundly disagree.

  13. The position I am defending here could therefore be seen as compatible with the evenhandedness approach to neutrality of treatment, see Patten, Equal Recognition, pp. 119–123.

  14. For the general view that religious commitments are not special vis-à-vis non-religious commitments, see Laborde (2017). McConnell (2000) provides a strong defense for the opposing view. For a critique of McConnell, see Boucher (2013, pp. 172–184).

  15. I distinguish religious instruction from religious education: the former aims at promoting a particular faith whereas latter takes a sociological or anthropological approach to religion, aims at familiarizing students with the phenomenon of religious belief and is often done under labels such as “Religions of the world", "Religious culture" or "Science of religions".

  16. On this conception of secularism, see Laborde (2008, p. 34) and Maclure and Taylor (2010, pp. 27–35).

  17. On the hands-off approach and the even-handed approaches to diversity, see Carens (2000, pp. 1–20, 77–87); Cf. Patten, Equal recognition, pp. 119–123.

References

  • Arneson, Richard. 2003. Liberal Neutrality on the Good: An Autopsy. In Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Political Theory, ed. Steven Wall and George Klosko, 191–218. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 2011. Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian. 2002. Culture and Equality. An Egalitarian Critique of Neutrality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, François. 2013. Exemptions to the Law, Freedom of Religion and Freedom of Conscience in Postsecular Societies. Philosophy and Public Issues 3(2): 159–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, Harry, and Adam Swift. 2006. Parents’ Rights and the Value of the Family. Ethics 117(1): 80–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, Harry, and Adam Swift. 2009. Legitimate Parental Partiality. Philosophy & Public Affairs 37(1): 43–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, Harry, and Adam Swift. 2014. Family Values. The Ethics of Parent–Child Relationship. Cambridge NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burtt, Shelley. 1994. Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defense of an Illiberal Education. The Review of Politics 56(1): 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burtt, Shelley. 1996. In defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools. In Nomos XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callan, Eamonn. 1997. Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carens, Joseph. 2000. Culture, Citizenship and Community. A Contextual exploration of Justice as Evenhandedness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, Matthew. 2006. Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, Matthew. 2012. Debate: The Case against the Comprehensive Enrolment of Children. Journal of Political Philosophy 20(3): 353–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cormier, Andrée-Anne. 2018. On the Permissibility of Shaping Children’s Values. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. 21(3): 333–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 2004. The God Delusion. Boston: Mariner Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumitru, Adelin Costin. 2018. Adequacy in Education and Normative School Choice. Studies in Philosophy and Education 37(2): 123–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Liberalism. In Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire, 113–143. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 2014. The Concept of Autonomy. In The Inner Citadel. Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. John Christman, 54–62. Brattleboro, VT: Echo Point Books & Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, James. 1999. Religious Schools Versus Children’s Rights. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisgruber, Christopher L., and Lawrence G. Sager. 2007. Religious Freedom and the Constitution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1980. The Child’s Right to an Open Future. In Whose Child? Children’s Right, Parental Authority, and State Power, ed. William Aiken and Hughe La Follette, 124–153. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Marilyn. 2003. Autonomy, Gender, Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William. 2002. Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy. 1995. Civic Education and Social Diversity. Ethics 105(3): 557–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy. 1999. Democratic Education. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, Will. 2001. Politics in the Vernacular. Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, Will. 2009. The Governance of Religious Diversity: The Old and the New. In International Migration and the Governance of Religious Diversity, ed. Paul Bramadat and Matthias Koenig, 323–334. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, Cécile. 2008. Critical Republicanism. The Hijab Controversy and Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, Cécile. 2017. Liberalism’s Religion. Oxford: Oxford university Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leiter, Brian. 2013. Why Tolerate Religion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Meira. 1999. The Demands of Liberal Education. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macedo, Stephen. 1995. Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls? Ethics 105(3): 468–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macedo, Stephen. 2003. Diversity and Distrust. Civic Education in a Multicultural Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar. 2000. Introduction: Refiguring Autonomy. In Relational Autonomy Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, 3–34. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, Colin. 1997. Conceptions of Parental Autonomy. Politics and Society 25(1): 117–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, Colin, and Benjamin Justice. 2016. Have a Little Faith. Religion, Democracy and the American Public Schools. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclure, Jocelyn, and Charles Taylor. 2010. Secularism and Freedom of Conscience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConnell, Michael W. 2000. The Problem of Singling Out Religion. De Paul Law Review 50: 1–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Claudia. 2003. The Child’s Right to an Open Future? Journal of Social Philosophy 34(4): 499–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modood, Tariq. 2009. Muslims, Religious Equality and Secularism. In Geoffrey Brahm Levey and Tariq Modood, ed. Religion Secularism and Multicultural Citizenship, 164–185. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patten, Alan. 2014. Equal Recognition. The Moral Foundation of Minority Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pena-Ruiz, Henri. 2005. Dieu et Marianne: Philosophie de la laïcité. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community. New York: Simon & Schuster Paperbacks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999a. The Law of Peoples: with The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999b. A theory of Justice, Revised ed. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinner, Jeff. 2000. Surviving Diversity: Religion and Democratic Citizenship. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstock, Daniel. 2016. A Freedom of Religion-Based Argument for Regulation of Religious Schools. In Religion and the Exercise of Public Authority, ed. Benjamin L. Berger and Richard Moon, 167–183. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstock, Daniel. 2018. For a Political Philosophy of Parent–Child Relationships. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 21(3): 351–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, Paul J. 2002. Religion and the Obligations of Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Patrick J., and Stephen Macedo (eds.). 2004. Educating Citizens: International Perspectives on Civic Values and School Choice. Washington: Brookings Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwarthoed, Danielle. 2015. Creating Frugal Citizens. The Liberal Egalitarian Case for Teaching Frugality. Theory and Research in Education 13(2): 286–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I have presented draft versions of this paper at different workshops, seminars and conferences at University College London, Université Laval, University of Montreal, and KU Leuven. I am especially thankful to Félix Aubé Beaudoin, Aurélia Bardon, Harry Brighouse, Andrée-Anne Cormier, Helder De Schutter, Marc-Antoine Dilhac, Valéry Giroux, Sarah Hannan, Eszter Kollar, Will Kymlicka, Cécile Laborde, Jocelyn Maclure, Félix Mathieu, Gina Schouten, Antoon Vandevelde, Daniel Weinstock, and Danielle Zwarthoed for valuable critical feedback and discussion. Any flaw in my argument is my entire responsibility and not theirs.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to François Boucher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boucher, F. Should Liberal States Subsidize Religious Schooling?. Stud Philos Educ 37, 595–613 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-018-9620-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-018-9620-9

Keywords

Navigation