Skip to main content
Log in

Peer effects in risk taking: Envy or conformity?

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We examine two explanations for peer effects in risk taking: relative payoff concerns and preferences that depend on peer choices. We vary experimentally whether individuals can condition a simple lottery choice on the lottery choice or the lottery allocation of a peer. We find that peer effects increase significantly, almost double, when peers make choices, relative to when they are allocated a lottery. In both situations, imitation is the most frequent form of peer effect. Hence, peer effects in our environment are explained by a combination of relative payoff concerns and preferences that depend on peer choices. Comparative statics analyses and structural estimation results suggest that a norm to conform to the peer may explain why peer choices matter. Our results suggest that peer choices are important in generating peer effects and hence have important implications for modeling as well as for policy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Peers might generally influence risk and other economic attitudes (Ahern et al. 2013). Peers also affect credit decisions (e.g., Banerjee et al. 2013; Georgarakos et al. 2012), savings decisions (e.g., Duflo and Saez 2002; Kast et al. 2012) as well as different teenager (risky) behaviors (for an overview, see Sacerdote 2011). Generally, peer effects are important in education (e.g., Sacerdote 2001; Duflo et al. 2011), in labor (e.g., Falk and Ichino 2006; Mas and Moretti 2009; Card et al. 2010), and pro-social behavior (e.g., Gächter et al. 2013).

  2. To increase the salience of complete information in our experiment, instructions were read aloud, for both potential roles in the experiment, and roles were assigned randomly within the same session. Also, we designed the lotteries to have at most two outcomes to minimize complexity. For a given probability distribution over the good and bad outcome, there were always six pairs of choices, which featured the exact same risky lottery. In half of the situations the safe lottery had two outcomes, and only one in the other half. The number of outcomes of the safe lottery, which can be viewed as a measure of complexity, does not have a significant influence on peer effects.

  3. There are a variety of studies examining social comparison effects in games such as public good games or coordination games (e.g., Falk and Fischbacher 2002; Falk et al. 2013). In social learning environments, Çelen and Kariv (2004) also study herding behavior, and identify substantial herding behavior.

  4. In terms of risk preferences B cannot be labeled as safe since it does not necessarily yield a certain payoff. In comparison to A, we still label it as safe, for simplicity, as its variance is always smaller. But note that a risk averse individual does not necessarily prefer B over A.

  5. Groups remain the same for the whole of Part II. All choices are made without any feedback until the end of the experiment. During Part I participants only know there will be a Part II in the experiment, but do not know anything about the decisions they will be asked to make. At the end of the experiment, individuals are informed about their payoff and, if Part II is drawn for payment, the choice and payoff of the other individual in the group. Throughout, we will refer to the peer as “she” and the decision maker as “he”.

  6. An alternative definition of peer effect is to consider only imitation and deviation (conditional strategies) as peer effects, since revisions could be due to mistakes. In Section 3.2 we examine both types of definitions and find qualitatively similar results.

  7. A similar control treatment was used by Cason and Mui (1998) to study social influence in dictator games. Also, we note that in the Coin treatment we can still examine four potential strategies of second movers in this treatment. However, in Coin the definition of imitation and deviation is arbitrary, as there is no direct link between the lottery choice of the decision maker and that of the peer.

  8. More specifically, we conducted a Base treatment, in which choices were made twice, in Part I and Part II, without the strategy method and without social feedback. We also conducted an Anticipation treatment, without the strategy method, but where individuals were aware they would be given feedback about the peer’s choice at the end of the experiment. Consistent with the effects of our main treatments, we observe peer effects increase significantly with anticipated social feedback, from occurring in 6.7% of the decisions in Base to 17.5% in the Anticipation treatment (Mann-Whitney test, p-value=0.016).

  9. We also included two additional choices to serve as controls for the certainty effect (Kahneman and Tversky 1979; Andreoni and Sprenger 2009). We analyze these decisions and the role of peers in a separate working paper.

  10. Instructions for all treatments are available in the Electronic Supplementary Materials on the journal’s website. The raw data as well as the z-tree codes are included in the Electronic Supplementary Material as well.

  11. To ensure credibility, one participant was randomly selected as assistant at the end of the experiment. The assistant drew one ball from an opaque bag containing balls corresponding to each part and from a second bag with balls corresponding to each decision problem. For each decision problem, the respective combination of black and white balls was put in an opaque bag and the assistant again drew one ball. Once all draws were done, payoffs were computed and subjects were paid out in cash.

  12. This literature started with Veblen (1899) and Duesenberry (1949), who argued that conspicuous consumption choices can be explained by a desire to signal a superior status, prowess or strength. A game-theoretic literature has focused on the implications of status concerns on conspicuous consumption (see, e.g., Hopkins and Kornienko 2004) and conformity (see, e.g., Bernheim 1994). Here we focus on ex-post payoff differences between the decision maker and his peer, and measure strategy choices of decision makers, who make conditional choices for each of the two possible lotteries of the peer. Related studies on social preferences under risk (e.g., Trautmann 2009; Saito 2013) point out that individuals may exhibit ex-ante relative payoff concerns, i.e. dislike inequality in expected payoffs. In our setting, such concerns yield qualitatively the same predictions, since risks are perfectly correlated. By choosing the lottery of the peer, decision makers can equalize expected payoffs both in Random and Choice.

  13. In the context of risk taking in the presence of others, whether individuals exhibit a desire to be ahead or not may depend on the situation (see Maccheroni et al. 2012, for a discussion). In our context, in which payoff differences are relatively small and the situation allows for a simple comparison with the peer, we would rather expect individuals dislike falling behind others, but enjoy being ahead. In Appendix A.1 we propose such a model in which decision makers are loss averse with respect to the peer’s outcome, and derive conditions under which peer effects are expected to occur. Note that assuming a dislike to being ahead of the peer would even strengthen the incentive to imitate the peer.

  14. One may also consider intention-based social preferences as an alternative explanation for why choices matter for relative payoff concerns (see, e.g., Blount 1995; Bolton et al. 2005; Falk and Fischbacher 2006). In our experiment there is no scope for reciprocity and it hence is unlikely that intention-based preferences are a driver of behavior. However, if intention-based social preferences would play a role, we would predict these to increase the weight on (negatively valued) payoff differences in the decision maker’s utility when moving from Random to Choice, which in expectation crucially depends on how A and B relate in terms of their expected values. Hence, moving from Random to Choice, not only would this theory predict imitation increases, but also that the increase in imitation depends on f. We do not find evidence for this in our data.

  15. According to Festinger, “an opinion, a belief, an attitude is ‘correct’, ‘valid’, and ‘proper’ to the extent that it is anchored in a group of people with similar beliefs, opinions and attitudes”; Festinger (1950), p. 272.

  16. See Appendix A.2 for a straightforward model based on social comparison theory.

  17. A detailed overview of choices in Part I is provided in Table 1 in Online Appendix C.1

  18. We also controlled for consistency of decisions in Part I. If we assume that subjects have CRRA preferences and given the design of our lotteries, we can classify second movers as consistent or inconsistent decision makers. We find across different probability panels, controlling for certainty, that at most 15.4% of decision patterns are inconsistent. If we exclude inconsistent decision makers from our sample our results remain qualitatively the same.

  19. At the individual level, the distribution of switching rates also differs across treatments. It is significantly different in Choice, compared to Random and Coin (Kolmogorov-Smirnov test, p-value=0.02 compared to Coin, p-value=0.09 compared to Random). But it does not differ significantly across Random and Coin (Kolmogorov-Smirnov test, p-value=0.96). Figure 1 in Online Appendix C.1 displays the distribution of switching rates by treatment.

  20. Table 2 in Online Appendix C.1 displays the frequency of each strategy choice for each decision, by treatment.

  21. In Random, the switching rate is close to 50%, since lotteries are randomly assigned to the peer with probability 0.5.

  22. We thank a referee for this suggestion.

  23. One might also argue that an increase in imitation from treatment Random to Choice might depend on the expected value of A relative to B. Intuitively, if agents exhibit relative payoff concerns and lottery B yields a higher expected payoff ( f < 1), the marginal increase in utility from imitation is stronger in magnitude in case the decision maker chooses B. This implies a stronger incentive to imitate B if f < 1 compared to f ≥ 1. We ran additional regressions, similar to the one presented in Table 4, distinguishing between lottery panels with f < 1, f > 1 and f = 1, and find that the interaction between Choice and imitation of B is only significant, and negative, when f = 1. That is, we do not find any systematic relationship between expected values and the increase in imitation. Details can be obtained from the authors upon request.

  24. Another approach could be to simultaneously estimate parameters defining relative payoff concerns and an additional utility from conforming to the social anchor. However, imitation (or deviation) can very generally be explained by a positive (or negative) estimate of γ as well as by λ > 1 (or λ < 1). Identifying both parameters, for both treatments simultaneously, is not possible with our data, but would be an interesting task for future work. Another approach might be to estimate mixture models, a procedure that we applied in a previous version of this paper. Mixture models have been used to estimate risk preferences in heterogeneous populations, amongst others by Conte et al. (2011) and Harrison and Rutström (2009). However, in our setting, assuming heterogeneity with respect to whether decision makers derive a social utility or not causes the following concern. The probability to be of a certain type enters into the log-likelihood function as a multiplicative weight of the social utility, and in this way scales the estimates of λ and γ. Moreover, it leaves one additional degree of freedom.

References

  • Ahern, K.R., Duchin, R., Shumway, T. (2013). Peer effects in economic attitudes. Working Paper.

  • Ai, C., & Norton, E.C. (2003). Interaction terms in logit and probit models. Economics Letters, 80(1), 123–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J., & Sprenger, C. (2009). Certain and uncertain utility: The Allais paradox and five decision theory phenomena. Working Paper.

  • Banerjee, A., Chandrasekhar, A.G., Duflo, E., Jackson, M.O. (2013). The diffusion of microfinance. Science, 341 (6144).

  • Bault, N., Coricelli, G., Rustichini, A. (2008). Interdependent utilities: How social ranking affects choice behavior. PLoS ONE, 3(10), e3477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B.D. (1994). A theory of conformity. Journal of Political Economy, 102(5), 841–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bikhchandani, S., Hirshleifer, D., Welch, I. (1998). Learning from the behavior of others: Conformity, fads, and informational cascades. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 12(3), 151–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blount, S. (1995). When social outcomes aren’t fair: The role of causal attributions on preferences. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 131–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, G.E., Brandts, J., Ockenfels, A. (2005). Fair procedures: Evidence from games involving lotteries. The Economic Journal, 115(506), 1054–1076.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandts, J., & Charness, G. (2000). Hot vs. cold: Sequential responses and preference stability in experimental games. Experimental Economics, 2, 227–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bursztyn, L., Ederer, F., Ferman, B., Yuchtman, N. (2014). Understanding mechanisms underlying peer effects: Evidence from a field experiment on financial decisions. Econometrica, 82(4), 1273–1301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cai, J., De Janvry, A., Sadoulet, E. (forthcoming). Social networks and the decision to insure. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics.

  • Cappelen, A.W., Konow, J., Sorensen, E.O., Tungodden, B. (2013). Just luck: An experimental study of risk taking and fairness. American Economic Review, 103(4), 1298–1413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Card, D., Mas, A., Moretti, E., Saez, E. (2010). Inequality at work: The effect of peer salaries on job satisfaction. NBER Working Paper.

  • Cason, T.N., & Mui, V.-L. (1998). Social influence in the sequential dictator game. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 42, 248–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Çelen, B., & Kariv, S. (2004). Observational learning under imperfect information. Games and Economic Behavior, 47(1), 72–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, R.B., & Goldstein, N.J. (2004). Social influence: Compliance and conformity. Annual Review of Psychology, 55(1), 591–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, R.B., & Trost, M.R. (1998). Social influence: Social norms, conformity and compliance. The Handbook of Social Psychology, 55(2), 151–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A.E., & Oswald, A.J. (1998). Comparison-concave utility and following behavior in social and economic settings. Journal of Public Economics, 70, 133–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conte, A., Hey, J.D., Moffatt, P. G. (2011). Mixture models of choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162(1), 79–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, D.J., & Rege, M. (2011). Misery loves company: Social regret and social interaction effects in choices under risk and uncertainty. Games and Economic Behavior, 73(1), 91–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duesenberry, J.S. (1949). Income, saving and the theory of consumer behavior. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duflo, E., Dupas, P., Kremer, M. (2011). Peer effects, teacher incentives, and the impact of tracking: Evidence from a randomized evaluation in kenya. American Economic Review, 101(5), 1739–1774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duflo, E., & Saez, E. (2002). Participation and investment decisions in a retirement plan: The influence of colleagues’ choices. Journal of Public Economics, 85, 121–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Fischbacher, U. (2002). “Crime” in the lab-detecting social interaction. European Economic Review, 46(4-5), 859–869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Fischbacher, U. (2006). A theory of reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 54(2), 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., Fischbacher, U., Gächter, S. (2013). Living in two neighborhoods – Social interaction effects in the laboratory. Economic Inquiry, 51(1), 563–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Ichino, A. (2006). Clean evidence on peer effects. Journal of Labor Economics, 24(1), 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K.M. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, L. (1950). Informal social communication. Psychology Review, 57, 271–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, L. (1954). A theory of social comparison processes. Human Relations, 7(2), 117–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 20(2), 171–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedl, A., Lima de Miranda, K., Schmidt, U. (2014). Insurance demand and social comparison: An experimental analysis. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 48(2), 97–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gächter, S., Nosenzo, D., Sefton, M. (2013). Peer effects in pro-social behavior: Social norms or social preferences? Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(3), 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galí, J. (1994). Keeping up with the joneses: Consumption externalities, portfolio choice, and asset prices. Journal of Money, Credit and Banking, 26(1), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gebhardt, G. (2004). Inequity aversion, financial markets, and output fluctuations. Journal of the European Economic Association, 2(2-3), 229–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gebhardt, G. (2011). Investment decisions with loss aversion over relative consumption. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 80(1), 68–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Georgarakos, D., Haliassos, M., Pasini, G. (2012). Household debt and social interactions. Working Paper.

  • Goeree, J.K., & Yariv, L (2007). Conformity in the lab. Working Paper.

  • Harrison, G W., & Rutström, E. (2009). Expected utility theory and prospect theory: One wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics, 12, 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, C.A., & Laury, S.K. (2002). Risk aversion and incentive effects. The American Economic Review, 92(5), 1644–1655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, H., Kubik, J.D., Stein, J.C. (2004). Social interaction and stock-market participation. The Journal of Finance, 59(1), 137–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, E., & Kornienko, T. (2004). Running to keep in the same place: Consumer choice as a game of status. The American Economic Review, 94(4), 1085–1107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kast, F., Meier, S., Pomeranz, D. (2012). Under-savers anonymous: Evidence on self-help groups and peer pressure as a savings commitment device. IZA Discussion Paper, 6311.

  • Linde, J., & Sonnemans, J. (2012). Social comparison and risky choices. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 44(1), 45–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Rustichini, A. (2012). Social decision theory: Choosing within and between groups. The Review of Economic Studies, 79, 1591–1636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C.F. (2000). Economic analysis of social interactions. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(3), 115–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas, A., & Moretti, E. (2009). Peers at work. The American Economic Review, 99(1), 112–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohde, I.M., & Rohde, K.I.M. (2011). Risk attitudes in a social context. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 43, 205–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacerdote, B. (2001). Peer effects with random assignment: Results for dartmouth roommates. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(2), 681–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacerdote, B. (2011). Peer effects in education: How might they work, how big are they and how much do we know thus far? Handbook of the Economics of Education, 46(3), 249–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saito, K. (2013). Social preferences under risk: Equality of opportunity versus equality of outcome. American Economic Review, 103(7), 3084–3101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiller, R.J. (1984). Stock prices and social dynamics. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 2, 457–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger, C (2012). An endowment effect for risk: Experimental tests of stochastic reference points. Working Paper.

  • Trautmann, S.T. (2009). A tractable model of process fairness under risk. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30(5), 803–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann, S.T., & Vieider, F. (2011). Social influences on risk attitudes: Applications in economics In Roeser, S. (Ed.), Handbook of Risk Theory: Springer.

  • Veblen, T.B. (1899). The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W.K., Phillips, O.R., Kroll, S. (2011). Risky investments decisions: How are individuals influenced by their groups? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 43, 81–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Kenneth Ahern, Jim Andreoni, Daniel Clarke, Dirk Engelmann, Florian Englmaier, Fabian Herweg, Alex Imas, Martin Kocher, Johannes Maier, Jan Potters, Justin Sydnor, Stefan Trautmann, Lise Vesterlund and Joachim Winter for their useful comments as well as seminar participants at Royal Holloway, University of Bamberg, University of Gothenburg, University of Innsbruck, University of Munich, University of Pittsburgh, at the 2014 AEA Meetings, 2012 CESifo Area Conference on Behavioural Economics, 2012 European and North-American ESA Meetings, 7th Nordic Conference in Behavioral and Experimental Economics in Bergen, ESI Workshop on Experimental Economics II, the CEAR/MRIC Behavioral Insurance Conference 2012, the Risk Preferences and Decisions under Uncertainty SFB 649 Workshop, the 2013 theem meeting in Kreutzlingen, and the 2013 Workshop on Behavioral and Experimental Economics in Florence. We gratefully acknowledge funding from the Fritz Thyssen Foundation (Project AZ.10.12.2.097).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marta Serra-Garcia.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 461 KB)

(ZIP 788 KB)

Appendix A: Theoretical framework

Appendix A: Theoretical framework

1.1 A.1 A model of relative payoff concerns

Assume the utility in state j ( j ∈ {g, b}) of having chosen lottery i ( i ∈ {A, B}) and earning \({m^{j}_{i}}\), to be given by the sum of two terms: a consumption utility, which is solely determined by individual risk preferences, plus a social utility term, which depends on payoff differences. This implies \(v^{j}_{i,k}=u\left ({m^{j}_{i}}\right ) + R\left ({m^{j}_{i}}-{m^{j}_{k}}\right ),\) where k ∈ {A, B} is the lottery of the peer, and R(⋅) is a function of payoff differences and defined as follows:

$$ R(x) = \left\{\begin{array}{ll} x & \text{if }x\geq0, \\ \lambda x & \text{if }x<0. \end{array}\right. $$

The parameter λ captures how large losses with respect to the peer loom relative to gains. An individual’s expected utility from choosing lottery i is

$$V_{i,k}=U_{i} + \sum\limits_{j} p_{j}R\left({m^{j}_{i}}-{m^{j}_{k}}\right), $$

where U i is the expected consumption utility of lottery i. If the peer holds a lottery that yields a lower consumption utility, the individual may nevertheless choose it, if he experiences a strong disutility from falling behind the peer, i.e. if λ is large enough. Let us define an individual’s strategy space as \(\mathcal {S}=\{\text {imitate} = (i; AA,BB),\, \text {deviate} = (i; BA,AB),\, \text {stay} = (i; iA,iB), \,\text {change} = (i; -iA,-iB); \,\text {for } i\in \{A,B\}\}\). Here i ( −i) denotes his (opposite) choice in Part I, and the tuple ik describes the choice of lottery i in Part II given that his peer has lottery k. Then, the cutoffs are given by the following proposition.

Proposition 1

Define \({\Delta }\equiv \frac {U_{B}-U_{A}}{p\delta }+\frac {(1-p)(c-\delta )}{p\delta }\) and \({\Theta }\equiv \frac {U_{A}-U_{B}}{(1-p)(c-\delta )}+\frac {p\delta }{(1-p)(c-\delta )}\) . An individual imitates if λ > max{Δ, Θ}. An individual deviates if λ< min{Θ, Δ}. An individual stays with his Part I choice otherwise.

Note that whether Δ is smaller or greater than Θ is determined by the individual’s choice in Part I, i.e. by his expected consumption utility U A and U B .

Proof

An individual imitates if V A, A > V B, A and V B, B > V A, B . V B, B > V A, B is equivalent to

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \lambda(1-p)(c-\delta)> U_{A}-U_{B}+p\delta\quad \Leftrightarrow \quad \lambda>{\Delta}\equiv\frac{U_{A}-U_{B}}{(1-p)(c-\delta)}+\frac{p\delta}{(1-p)(c-\delta)}. \end{array} $$

V A, A > V B, A is equivalent to

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \lambda p\delta&>U_{B}-U_{A}+(1-p)(c-\delta)\quad \Leftrightarrow \quad \lambda>{\Theta}\equiv\frac{U_{B}-U_{A}}{p\delta}+\frac{(1-p)(c-\delta)}{p\delta}. \end{array} $$

Hence, for an individual to imitate it must hold that λ > max{Δ, Θ}.

Similarly, an individual deviates if V A, A < V B, A and V B, B < V A, B . It follows directly from above that this is satisfied if λ < min{Δ, Θ}. □

1.2 A.2 A model based on social comparison theory

Consider a model in which the closer the individual risky choice is to the social anchor, the more utility the individual derives. In a setting with only two options, this can be captured by an additional utility γ when the option chosen coincides with the social anchor. In particular, the expected utility of lottery i given the anchor k is

$$V_{i,k}=U_{i} +\gamma \cdot\mathbf{1}(i=k), $$

where 1(⋅) is the indicator function. (Cooper and Rege, 2011, also assume this form of utility when examining conformity.) Based on the argument above, we would expect γ to differ across treatments and γ C , in Choice, to be larger than γ R , in Random. This would generate an increase in imitation in Choice. Further, since the effect of γ is independent of lottery characteristics, we would expect the change in imitation across treatments to be symmetric with respect to the two available options, A or B.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lahno, A.M., Serra-Garcia, M. Peer effects in risk taking: Envy or conformity?. J Risk Uncertain 50, 73–95 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-015-9209-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-015-9209-4

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation