Skip to main content
Log in

The arguments of utility: Preference reversals in expected utility of income models

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a debate in the literature about the arguments of utility in expected utility theory. Some implicitly assume utility is defined on final wealth whereas others argue it may be defined on initial wealth and income separately. I argue that making income and wealth separate arguments of utility has important implications that may not be widely recognized. A framework is presented that allows the unified treatment of expected utility models and anomalies. I show that expected utility of income models can predict framing induced preference reversals, a willingness to pay-willingness to accept gap for lotteries, and choice-value preference reversals. The main contribution is a theorem. It is proved that for all utility functions where initial wealth and income enter separately, either there will be preference reversals or preferences can be represented by a utility function defined on final wealth alone.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Other authors have also presented expected utility models that are explicitly not defined on wealth alone. An early example is Markowitz (1952) and a more recent one Sugden (2003).

  2. Another response to Rabin’s paradox is the argument that other theories are vulnerable to analogous calibrations, so calibration may be a problem for all decision theories, not just expected utility of final wealth. Cox and Sadiraj (2006) present a concavity calibration proposition for small and large stake risk aversion that applies to expected utility of income models and some non-expected utility theories. Rubinstein (2006) considers time preferences and presents a calibration showing how constant discounting and seemingly plausible inter-day discounting predict implausible degrees of discounting over longer periods.

  3. This analogy was introduced by Tversky and Kahneman (1981).

  4. In Section 2.2 the state-by-state approach is compared to an approach similar to that taken by Koszegi and Rabin (2007).

  5. The potential for anomalies does not go unnoticed by Cox and Sadiraj. For instance in their footnote 8 they write that the expected utility of initial wealth and income model they introduce “does not rule out certain types of anomalies (see Rubinstein 2006 for an illustration). Detailed analysis of possible “money pump” preference cycles and other violations of full rationality are beyond the scope of the present paper, which is concerned with the implications of concavity calibration for decision theories.”

  6. This example is a slight modification of one Kahneman and Tversky (1982) use. It shows how the same decision problem can be framed in different ways and how different frames can lead people to choose different options.

  7. It would be a simple extension to include an act representing background risk.

  8. Other aspects of Koszegi and Rabin’s model (such as separating standard consumption utility and loss gain utility and making the reference point a person’s recent rational expectations about outcomes) are not used in this paper.

  9. That choice-value preference reversals can occur in an expected utility model is not a new result. For instance, Sugden (2003) shows how similar results occur in an expected utility model where utility is defined on satisfaction and changes in satisfaction.

  10. See Wakker (2008) for a discussion of the characteristics of such functions.

References

  • Andersen, S., Harrison, G.W., Lau, M.I., Rutström, E.E. (2008). Eliciting risk and time preferences. Econometrica, 76, 583–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, I., Munro, A., Rhodes, B., Starmer, C., Sugden, R. (1997). A test of the theory of reference-dependent preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 479–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, J.C., & Sadiraj, V. (2006). Small-and large-stakes risk aversion: Implications of concavity calibration for decision theory. Games and Economic Behavior, 56, 45–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt, R.P., Munro, A., Starmer, C. (2004). Testing explanations of preference reversal. The Economic Journal, 114, 709–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., & Levine, D.K. (2006). A dual-self model of impulse control. American Economic Review, 96, 1449–1476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grether, D.M., & Plott, C.R. (1979). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. The American Economic Review, 69, 623–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, G.W., List, J.A., Towe, C. (2007). Naturally occurring preferences and exogenous laboratory experiments: A case study of risk aversion. Econometrica, 75, 433–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, C.A., & Laury, S.K. (2002). Risk aversion and incentive effects. American Economic Review, 92, 1644–1655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). The psychology of preferences. Scientific American, 246, 160–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J.L., Thaler, R.H. (1990). Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the coase theorem. Journal of Political Economy, 98(6), 1325–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J.L. (1989). The endowment effect and evidence of nonreversible indifference curves. American Economic Review, 79, 1277–1284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2007). Reference-dependent risk attitudes. American Economic Review, 97, 1047–1073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, J.A. (2003). Does market experience eliminate market anomalies? The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118, 41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markowitz, H. (1952). The utility of wealth. Journal of Political Economy, 60, 151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, J.W. (1964). Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica, 32, 122–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68, 1281–1281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M., & Thaler, R.H. (2001). Anomalies: Risk aversion. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15, 219–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (2006). Dilemmas of an economic theorist. Econometrica, 74, 865–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.J. (1954). The foundation of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U., Starmer, C., Sugden, R. (2008). Third-generation prospect theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 36, 203–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2003). Reference-dependent subjective expected utility. Journal of Economic Theory, 111, 172–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P. (2005). Formalizing reference dependence and initial wealth in Rabin’s calibration theorem. http://people.few.eur.nl/wakker/pdf/calibcsocty05.pdf.

  • Wakker, P.P. (2008). Explaining the characteristics of the power (CRRA) utility family. Health Economics, 17, 1329–1344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P. (2010). Prospect theory: For risk and ambiguity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Thomas Epper, Jacob Goeree, Konrad Mierendorff, Chris Starmer, Jingjing Zhang, and participants at the FUR XIV International Conference at Newcastle University, as well as the editor and one anonymous referee, for comments. I would like to thank the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant SNSF 138162) and the European Research Council (grant ESEI-249433) for financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luke Lindsay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lindsay, L. The arguments of utility: Preference reversals in expected utility of income models. J Risk Uncertain 46, 175–189 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-013-9162-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-013-9162-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation