Skip to main content
Log in

Deliberative Democracy, Diversity, and Restraint

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Public reason liberals disagree about the relationship between public justification and deliberative democracy. My goal is to argue against the recent suggestion that public reason liberals seek a ‘divorce’ from deliberative democracy. Defending this thesis will involve discussing the benefits of deliberation for public justification as well as revisiting public reason’s standard Rawlisan restraint requirement. I criticize Kevin Vallier’s alternative convergence-based principle of restraint and respond to the worry that the standard Rawlsian restraint requirement reduces the likelihood of public justification by limiting the diversity of inputs into the justificatory process.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Rawls (2005, p. 448). See also Cohen (1997, p. 72); Freeman (2000, p. 377); Quong (2011, pp. 256–260); and Schwartzman (2011, pp. 381–382).

  2. There is a general discussion of majority rule at Rawls (1999, pp. 313–318).

  3. For concerns about institutionalizing this standard, see especially Gaus and Van Schoelandt (2017, pp. 167–171).

  4. I do not suggest that decisions are legitimate only if they are in fact correct according to some standard independent of democratic procedures. Rather, the legitimacy of democracy depends on aiming at getting things right, according to such standards (Estlund 2008, p. 102; Landemore 2013, p. 219).

  5. Providing necessary and sufficient conditions for what counts as a ‘public’ reason, or a relevant justifying (or defeater) reason for public justification, is obviously a matter of controversy among public reason liberals. Here I stipulate what I believe to be the most plausible account, though I have not provided a defense of it.

  6. In my view, reasons are accessible when they can be meaningfully evaluated in light of standards shared by citizens generally, such as reliable perception and observation, rules of inference, common sense, scientific methodology and evidence, quantitative reasoning, jurisprudential reasoning, historical evidence, and shared democratic political values. I assume that some degree of idealization must be associated with categorizing reasons as accessible, so that reasons are accessible to citizens with at least modestly developed capacities to evaluate evidence of this sort. For a contrasting view that rejects any idealization as part of accessibility, see Laborde (2017, p. 121). For a convergence conception of moderate idealization that rejects the accessibility standard altogether, see Vallier (2014, pp. 145–180).

  7. Gaus expresses doubts about whether, given its assumptions, the Hong-Page model could be applied to disagreements about justice among persons with diverse evaluative standpoints (2016, pp. 114–131).

  8. I have assumed but not defended the claim that scientific reasoning is generally accessible. For discussion see Leland and van Wietmarschen (2012) and Jønch-Clausen and Kappel (2016).

  9. These considerations are part of a general argument against democracy in Brennan (2016).

References

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2006. The Epistemology of Democracy. Episteme 3: 8–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billingham, Paul. 2016. Convergence Justifications Within Political Liberalism: A Defence. Res Publica 22: 135–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, Colin. 2014. Coercion and Public Justification. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 13: 189–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonotti, Matteo. 2017. Partisanship and Political Liberalism in Diverse Societies. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1997. Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy. In Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, ed. James Bohman and William Rehg, 67–92. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1986. The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory. In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Jon Elster and Aanund Hylland, 103–132. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, Samuel. 2000. Deliberative Democracy: A Sympathetic Comment. Philosophy & Public Affairs 29: 371–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald, and Kevin Vallier. 2009. The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity: The Implications of Convergence, Asymmetry and Political Institutions. Philosophy and Social Criticism 35: 51–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald, and Chad Van Schoelandt. 2017. Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political Liberalism. Ethics 128: 145–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald. 2016. The Tyranny of the Ideal. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert. 2003. Reflective Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert. 2008. Innovating Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms, trans. William Rehg. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

  • Hong, Lu, and Scott Page. 2004. Groups of Diverse Problem Solvers Can Outperform Groups of High-Ability Problem Solvers. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences 101: 16385–16389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jønch-Clausen, Karin, and Klemens Kappel. 2016. Scientific Facts and Methods in Public Reason. Res Publica 22: 117–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, Cécile. 2017. Liberalism’s Religion. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2013. Democratic Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène, and Scott Page. 2015. Deliberation and disagreement: Problem Solving, Prediction, and Positive Dissensus. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 14: 229–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leland, R.J., and Han van Wietmarschen. 2012. Reasonableness, Intellectual Modesty, and Reciprocity in Political Justification. Ethics 122: 721–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, Jane. 2009. A ‘Seletion Model’ of Political Representation. Journal of Political Philosophy 17: 369–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, John, and Jane Mansbridge. 2012. Deliberative Systems. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pitkin, Hanna. 1967. The Concept of Representation. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice, rev. edn. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2005. Political Liberalism, exp. edn. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy, David. 2000. Rawls’s Wide View of Public Reason: Not Wide Enough. Res Publica 6: 49–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism without Perfection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzman, Micah. 2011. The Sincerity of Public Reason. Journal of Political Philosophy 19: 375–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallier, Kevin. 2014. Liberal Politics and Public Faith. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vallier, Kevin. 2015. Public Justification versus Public Deliberation: The Case for Divorce. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45: 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Boettcher.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boettcher, J. Deliberative Democracy, Diversity, and Restraint. Res Publica 26, 215–235 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-019-09435-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-019-09435-2

Keywords

Navigation