Advertisement

International Journal for Philosophy of Religion

, Volume 76, Issue 2, pp 171–191 | Cite as

Religious diversity and epistemic luck

  • Max Baker-Hytch
Article

Abstract

A familiar criticism of religious belief starts from the claim that a typical religious believer holds the particular religious beliefs she does just because she happened to be raised in a certain cultural setting rather than some other. This claim is commonly thought to have damaging epistemological consequences for religious beliefs, and one can find statements of an argument in this vicinity in the writings of John Stuart Mill and more recently Philip Kitcher, although the argument is seldom spelled out very precisely. This paper begins by offering a reconstruction of an argument against religious beliefs from cultural contingency, which proceeds by way of an initial argument to the unreliability of the processes by which religious beliefs are formed, whose conclusion is then used to derive two further conclusions, one which targets knowledge and the other, rationality. Drawing upon recent work in analytic epistemology, I explore a number of possible ways of spelling out the closely related notions of accidental truth, epistemic luck, and reliability upon which the argument turns. I try to show that the renderings of the argument that succeed in securing the sceptical conclusion against religious beliefs also threaten scepticism about various sorts of beliefs besides religious beliefs.

Keywords

Religious diversity Cultural contingency Epistemic luck Reliability Undercutting defeater Knowledge 

References

  1. Becker, K. (2007). Epistemology modalized. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Becker, K. (2008). Epistemic luck and the generality problem. Philosophical Studies, 139, 353–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bogardus, T. (2013). The problem of contingency for religious belief. Faith and Philosophy, 30(4), 371–392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dretske, F. (1971). Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49(1), 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Gellman, J. (1993). Religious diversity and the epistemic justification of religious belief. Faith and Philosophy, 10(3), 345–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Kitcher, P. (2011). Challenges for secularism. In G. Levine (Ed.), The joy of secularism: 11 essays for how we live now (pp. 24–56). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Kuhn, T. S. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2010). Unreasonable knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Mawson, T. J. (2009). Mill’s argument against religious knowledge. Religious Studies, 45(4), 417–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Mill, J. S. (1991). On liberty. In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The collected works of John Stuart Mill (Vol. XVIII). Toronto: Toronto University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Plantinga, A. (1995). Pluralism: A defence of religious exclusivism. In T. D. Senor (Ed.), The rationality of belief and the plurality of faith: Essays in honor of William P. Alston (pp. 191–215). London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Plantinga, A. (1997). Ad Hick. Faith and Philosophy, 14(3), 295–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Pollock, J. L. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  19. Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Pritchard, D. (2009). Safety-based epistemology: Wither now? Journal of Philosophical Research, 34, 33–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Pritchard, D. (2012). Anti-luck virtue epistemology. Journal of Philosophy, 109(3), 247–279.Google Scholar
  22. Stalnaker, R. C. (1975). Causation and conditionals. In E. Sosa (Ed.), Oxford readings in philosophy (pp. 165–179). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. van Inwagen, P. (1995). Non est Hick. In T. D. Senor (Ed.), The rationality of belief and the plurality of faith: Essays in honor of William P. Alston (pp. 216–241). London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Williamson, T. (2009). Reply to John Hawthorne and Maria Lasonen-Aarnio. In P. Greenough & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Williamson on knowledge (pp. 313–329). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Williamson, T. (2014). Knowledge first. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 1–10). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculty of PhilosophyUniversity of OxfordOxford United Kingdom

Personalised recommendations