Skip to main content
Log in

Mises and prediction markets: Can markets forecast?

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

Ludwig von Mises’s methodological position is unique because it combines apriorism with qualitative empirical approach. Nonetheless, Mises’s adherents and detractors continue to characterize his apriorism as rejecting forecasting. This paper argues that a prediction market is a traditional market for forward-looking information; it leverages subjective knowledge and aggregates information via the market process to effectively solve the Hayekian knowledge problem. We argue that Austrian economists should embrace prediction markets as a powerful method of forecasting rooted in human action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Please, see Block (1999, 2003), Caplan (1999, 2001, 2003), and Hülsmann (1999).

  2. See, for example, Hoppe (2007, 1997), Kirzner (1997), O’Driscoll and Rizzo (1996), and Vaughn (1994). When Caplan (2001) discusses the Austrian tradition of empirical analysis, he suggests delineating the term “Misesian” among the Austrian economists. Caplan uses the term “Misesian” in reference to the strand of Austrian economics influenced by both Mises and Rothbard that rejects empirical (a posteriori) analysis of economic laws.

  3. Prediction markets are also known as “information markets” or “event futures” (see Wolfers and Zitzewitz 2004; Hanson 1991; 1990).

  4. See, for example, von Mises’ Human Action (1944[1996]) and Epistemological Problems of Economics (1978 [1933]), as well as Murray Rothbard’s Man, Economy and State ([1962]1993).

  5. See Langlois (1994), Mises (1996; 1978; 1957), Rothbard (1993), and Knight (1921).

  6. Knight (1921: 233) defined measurable uncertainty (i.e., class probability) as risk, and unmeasurable uncertainty (i.e., case probability) as uncertainty He asserted that the probability calculus was applicable to both risk (class probability) and uncertainty (case probability). In the context of case probability, Knight noted that subjective probability required two stages: “the formation of an estimate and the estimation of its value” (ibid: 227). While the first stage is a qualitative judgment, the second stage is a quantitative evaluation.

  7. In the 1970s Lucas’ critique (1976) restated a long-held position of Mises on estimation of economic constants. Neoclassical and Austrian economists agree that human action cannot have economic constants because the dimensions of human actions are unique (Barnett 2003; Mises, 1996; Friedman 1953).

  8. Ludwig von Mises (1996: 109) argued that the frequentist probability was “the only logically satisfactory one” because one could attain it through the deductive aprioristic theory. Crovelli (2010: 2) writes that “for most Austrians who have discussed Ludwig von Mises’ theory of probability (including this author [himself], to some extent) it has been common to label Ludwig von Mises as a proponent of the “frequentist” interpretation of probability advanced by his brother, Richard von Mises.”.

  9. Dice have no memory, so one can induce the odds of rolling two sixes in a row. This is not limited to cases of induction. A die can be weighted so that it comes up on six with more or less than a 1/6 probability, but coins, by the laws of physics, cannot be so weighted (Gelman and Nolan 2002). The probability of flipping heads that is ½ is apodictically certain because it is derived through the deductive aprioristic theory.

  10. We thank an anonymous referee for these comments.

  11. A similar phenomenon occurs regularly during the game show Who Wants to be a Millionaire. When a contestant is stumped by a trivia question, the contestant can choose to ask a friend (an expert) or ask the audience. The expert is correct 65 % of the time; the audience is correct 91 % of the time.

  12. This example shows that insider-trading reveals information in the most efficient way. See, for example: Block and McGee (1992) and McGee and Block (2004).

  13. Some prediction markets use virtual currency like Hollywood Stock Exchange or Foresight Exchange. Does money improve predictions? Servan-Schreiber et al. (2004) conclude that real money does not really matter in forecasting sports events. In contrast, Rosenbloom and Notz (2006) find that real-money markets are significantly more accurate for non-sports events. So far empirical evidence is mixed. It can be a result of two opposing market forces. Profit-seeking self-interest motivates real-money market predictions while minimum transaction costs and intrinsic value motivate play-money market predictions.

  14. IEM is a low-risk market because it limits traders to $500 position. Other prediction markets such as Economic Derivatives that do not limit trading positions turn over hundreds of millions of dollars.

  15. Wolfers and Zitzewitz (2004) define three main types of contracts used in prediction markets: winner-takes-all, index, and spread. Winner-takes-all contract reveals market expectations of probability that event occurs. Index and spread contracts reveal market expectations of mean and median value of outcome.

  16. Can you manipulate prediction markets? In the recent review article Wolfers and Zitzewitz (2004) conclude that none of price manipulations “had much of a discernible effect on prices, except during a short transition phase.”

References

  • Barnett, W., II. (2003). Dimensions and Economics: Some Problems. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 6(3), 27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, J., R., Forsythe, F., Nelson and T., Rietz. (2001). Results from a Dozen Years of Election Futures Markets Research. in C., Plott and V., Smith (Eds) Handbook of Experimental Economic Results.

  • Block, W. (1999). Austrian Theorizing: Recalling the Foundations. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 2, 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, W. (2003). Realism: Austrian vs. Neoclassical Economics, Reply to Caplan. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 6(3), 47–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, W., & McGee, R. W. (1992). Insider Trading. In R. W. McGee (Ed.), Business Ethics and Common Sense (pp. 219–229). New York: Quorum Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. (Ed.). (1994). The Elgar Companion to Austrian Economics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. (1998). Ludwig von Mises. In J. Davis, D. Wade Hands, & U. Maki (Eds.), The Handbook of Economic Methodology. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. J. (2001). Calculation and coordination. PAGE. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. J. (2010). Handbook on Contemporary Austrian Economics. Northhampton: Edward Elger.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P., & Prychitko, D. (Eds.). (1994). The market process : Essays in contemporary Austrian economics. USA: E. Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (1999). The Austrian Search for Realistic Foundations. Southern Economic Journal, 65(4), 823–838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2001). Probability, Common Sense, and Realism: A Reply to Hülsmann and Block. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 4(2), 69–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2003). Probability and the Synthetic A Priori: A Reply to Block. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 6(3), 77–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crovelli, M. (2010). A Challenge to Ludwig von Mises’ Theory of Probability. Libertarian Papers, 2(23), 2–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forsythe, R., Nelson, F., Neumann, G. R., & Wright, J. (1992). Anatomy of an Experimental Political Stock Market. American Economic Review, 82, 1142–1161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1953). Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, A., & Nolan, D. (2002). You Can Load a Die, But You Can’t Bias a Coin. The American Statistician, 56(4), 308–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, R. (1990). Market-based foresight: A proposal. Foresight Update, 10, 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, R. (1991). More market-based foresight. Foresight Update, 11, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35(4), 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoppe, H. (1997). On Certainty and Uncertainty, Or: How Rational Can Our Expectations Be? Review of Austrian Economics, 10(1), 49–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoppe, H. (2007). The Limits of Numerical Probability: Frank H. Knight and Ludwig Von Mises and the Frequency Interpretation. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 10(1), 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hülsmann, J. G. (1999). Economic Science and Neoclassicism. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 2(4), 3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. (1997). Entrepreneurial discovery and the competitive market process: An Austrian approach. Journal of Economic Literature, 35, 60–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. (1921). Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lachmann, L. (1994). Expectations and the meaning of institutions: Essays in economics. London: Rutledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langlois, R. (1994). Risk and uncertainty. In P. Boettke (Ed.), The Elgar companion to Austrian economics (pp. 118–122). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P., & Boettke, P. J. (2006). Was Mises Rights? Review of Social Economy, 2, 247–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, P. (2001). The Development of Austrian Economics: Revisiting the Neoclassical Divide. Review of Austrian Economics, 14(4), 239–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, P. (2012). What do We Know for Certain about Uncertainty? The Legatum Institute Charles Street Symposium, June 10.

  • Lucas, R. (1976). Econometric Policy Evaluation: A Critique. Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy 1.

  • McGee, R., & Block, W. (2004). An Ethical and Economic Look at Insider Trading. In A. de Wolf (Ed.), Ordered Anarchy: Festschrift Essays in Honor of Anthony de Jasay. Arlington: Singularity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Driscoll, G., & Rizzo, M. (1996). The Economics of Time and Ignorance. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, B., & Stringham, E. (2012). Radical Scholarship Taking on the Mainstream: Murray Rothbard’s Contribution. Review of Austrian Economics, 25, 315–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll, R. (1984). Orange juice and weather. American Economic Review, 74, 861–880.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbloom, E. S., & Notz, W. (2006). Statistical Tests of Real-Money versus Play-Money Prediction Markets. Electronic Markets, 16(1), 63–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M. ([1962]1993). Man, economy, and state: A treatise on economic principles. Auburn, AL: Mises Institute.

  • Rothbard, M. (1979). Thy Myth of Efficiency. In M. Rizzo (Ed.), Time, Uncertainty, and Disequilibrium. Lexington, MA: DC Heath.

  • Rothbard, M. (1991). The End of Socialism and the Calculation Debate Revisited. Review of Austrian Economics, 5(2), 51–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M. (2011). Economic Controversies. Auburn: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Servan-Schreiber, E., Wolfers, J., Pennock, D., & Galebach, B. (2004). Prediction Markets: Does Money Matter. Electronic Markets, 14(3), 243–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snowberg, E., Wolfers, J., & Zitzewitz, E. (2007). Partisan Impact on the Economy: Evidence from Prediction Markets and Close Elections. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 122(2), 807–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stasser, G., & Titus, W. (1985). Pooling of Unshared Information in Group Decision Making: Biased Information Sampling During Discussion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48(6), 1467–1478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surowiecki, J. (2004). The Wisdom of Crowds. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1992). The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H. (1992). Microeconomic analysis. New York: W. W Norton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughn, K. (1994). Austrian economics in America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. ([1928] 1957). Probability, statistics, and truth. New York: Dover

  • von Mises, L. ([1933] 1978). Epistemological Problems of Economics, Jena: Gustav Fischer

  • von Mises, L. ([1949] 1996). Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press

  • von Mises, L. (1957). Theory and History. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1975). Markets and hierarchies: analysis and antitrust implications. New York/London: Free.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfers, J., & Zitzewitz, E. (2004). Prediction Markets. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 18(2), 107–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leonid Krasnozhon.

Additional information

We would like to thank William Barnett II, Walter Block, Daniel J. D’Amico, and anonymous referee for helpful comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Krasnozhon, L., Levendis, J. Mises and prediction markets: Can markets forecast?. Rev Austrian Econ 28, 41–52 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-013-0244-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-013-0244-6

Keywords

JEL Codes

Navigation