Skip to main content
Log in

Irreducible complexities: from Gödel and Turing to the paradigm of Imperfect Knowledge Economics

  • Published:
Quality & Quantity Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper discusses synthetically an epistemological question in the field of economics: how to translate a real problem into formal terms without a substantial loss of significance for its solution in policy making. The discussion will challenge the plausibility of the basic assumption of ultra-rational subjects who act independently of each other and will propose a research programme in Imperfect Knowledge Economics (in an Appendix the latter is compared with the mainstream model founded on Rational Expectation Hypothesis). References to some results of the debate in mathematics, but also in computer science, are produced in support.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Term derives from Latin translation of al-Khwārizmī (pronounced in classical Arabic as Al-Khwarithmi), the place of birth (nisba) of Persian mathematician Abū Ja‘far Muhammad ibn Mūsā al-Khwārizmī.

  2. Douglas R. Hofstadter (Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid, 1979) compared Gödel’s arguments to the works of the Dutch artist, Maurits C. Escher (an exhibition of Escher’ works was held in conjunction with the 1954 International congress of mathematicians in Amsterdam), and in particular to Drawing hands (1948), which depicts two hands drawing each other (a self-referential paradox, loop logic that is not included in Hilbert’s programme). Nevertheless, Gödel’s theorem positions itself at a completely different level to Heisenberg’s (1927), which was the key to quantum mechanics and confirmed the impossibility of applying deterministic forecasts to the microscopic world of atoms and particles, thus posing a generally inaccessible limit on the possibility of knowing the most secret aspects of nature and introducing elements of unpredictability, even real non-causality, in the scientific view of the world.

  3. See Feferman (2006); Lolli (2011).

  4. Interesting developments in Cambridge (UK) have influenced J.M. Keynes’s thought. See Simili (1987).

  5. An example is Markov’s chain, which is the basis of the Pagerank, Google’s algorithm that quantifies the popularity of a site (through the number of links in other sites that point to the page in question). These chains indicate stochastic processes in which the probability of moving to a state in the system depends entirely on the immediately preceding state and not on how that state has been reached (Markov’s property or condition of “memorylessness”), for whom, so to speak, the future is independent of the past once the present situation is assigned (a situation that does not apply in cases in which “real” time counts. The context tends to be —to use Samuelson’s term, adapted from statistical mechanics —“not ergodic”, that is, path dependence holds).

  6. In Sect. 5 we will return to the question of uncertainty in a strong sense à la Knight and Keynes who excluded the very possibility of calculating probability and relied on the degree of belief in future events that is reasonable to nurture on the basis of data available and social conventions.

  7. On the topic of epistemological implications of economic complexity useful suggestions can be found in a reference list that includes, in different ways, Blaug (1980); Debreu (1987); Hausman (1992); Hausman (1994); Hicks (1979); Ingrao and Israel (1990); Kaldor (1975); Kay (2011); Kirman (2010); Lunghini (2002); Marshall (1920); Mill (1836), Pigou (1920); Pigou (1951); Solow (1956); Stewart (2012).

  8. According to the so-called “Duhem–Quine thesis” (formulated by the physicist Duhem as early as in 1906 and taken up by the American philosopher Quine in 1951), no theory can be compared with experience in isolation, as it is in fact necessary for an experimentum crucis. Therefore, it follows that a conclusive empirical falsification is not possible for single scientific propositions and that there exists the hypothesis that all theoretical statements, not only scientific ones, do not have a separate meaning. The conclusion, of a holistic type, is that only language as a unitary whole is really significant (http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html). See Boylan and O’Gorman (1998); Boylan and O’Gorman (2003). It is interesting to note how this position was criticized by one of Quine’s pupils, David Lewis, who used the game theory in a paper in 1969 to study conventions (a topic very close to Keynes, as stressed, among others, by Davis 1997). “Common knowledge” happens through coordination games; language can be understood as a signalling game.

  9. To complete the picture we have on the policy side flexible inflation targeting (Fit) that dictates rather simple and automatic rules of conduct for monetary authority based on the pursuit of price stability and the principle of zero-budget on the fiscal front.

  10. As Keynes wrote—clearly alluding to Newtonian physics—in a letter to R.F. Harrod of 16 July 1938, “It is as though the fall of an apple to the ground depended on the apple’s motives, on whether it is worth while falling to the ground, and whether the ground wanted the apple to fall, and on mistaken calculations on the part of the apple as to how far it was from the centre of the earth” (CW, 1971–1989, vol. XIV, p. 300). A part of the uncertainty about the speed of the fall can be attributed to mathematical errors by the apple (“mistaken calculations”) which can generally be corrected. However, the main ‘human’ characteristics which Keynes attributes to his apple are “motivations” and “intentions”: these make economics a “moral”, not a “natural” science.

  11. The following extract from an article by Rodrik called Occupy the Classroom? (December 12, 2011) is particularly significant: “economists get stuck with the charge of being narrowly ideological, because they are their own worst enemy when it comes to applying their theories to the real world. Instead of communicating the full panoply of perspectives that their discipline offers, they display excessive confidence in particular remedies... In our zeal to display the profession’s crown jewels in untarnished form—market efficiency, the invisible hand, comparative advantage—we skip over the real-world complications and nuances, well recognized as they are in the discipline”. It ends: “It is as if introductory physics courses assumed a world without gravity, because everything becomes so much simpler that way... the economics we need is... not the “rule-of-thumb” kind. It is an economics that recognizes its limitations”.

  12. Very stimulating is the reference to Karl Popper that notes: “In all these cases the propensity theory of probability allows us to work with an objective theory of probability. Quite apart from the fact that we do not know the future, the future is objectively not fixed. The future is open: Objectively open. Only the past is fixed; it has been actualised and so it is gone. The present can be described as the continuing process of the actualisation of propensities; or, more metaphorically, of the freezing or the crystallization of propensities. While the propensities actualize or realize themselves, they are continuing processes... Propensities, like Newtonian attractive forces, are invisible and, like them, they can act: they are actual, they are real” (Popper 1990, p. 18—emphasis in the original).

  13. If \(P_t\) refers to a share, \(X_{t}\) is a set of dividend, whereas \(a_{t} = 0, \,b_{t} = c_{t} =\) discount rate. If \(P_t\) refers to exchange rates, \(X_{t}\) is the levels of domestic minus foreign money supply and income, whereas \(b_{t}\) and \(c_{t}\) depend on the interest elasticity of money demand.

  14. For notational ease the superscript “IK” on representations on the individual level is omitted.

References

  • Aumann, R.J., Hart, S. (eds.): Handbook of Game Theory, Elsevier, Amsterdam (first volume 1992, second volume 1994, third volume 2002)

  • Becker, G.S.: The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago University Press, Chicago (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, F., Scholes, M.: The pricing of options and corporate liabilities. J. Polit. Econ. 81(3), 637–654 (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug, M.: The Methodology of Economics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1980)

  • Boylan, T.A., O’Gorman, P.F.: The Duhem–Quine Thesis in Economics: A reinterpretation, Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, Boston, 10–15 August 1998

  • Boylan, T.A., O’Gorman, P.F.: Pragmatism in economic methodology: the Duhem-Quine thesis revisited. Found. Sci. 8, 3–21 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J.B.: J.M. Keynes on history and convention. In: Harcourt, G.C., Riach, P. (eds.) A Second Edition of The General Theory. Routledge, London (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: Mathematical economics. In: Eatwell, J., Milgate, M., Newman, P. (eds.) The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, vol. 3, pp. 399–404. Macmillan, London (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P.M.M.: La théorie physique: son object et sa structure. Chevalier & Riviére, Paris (1906)

  • Fama, E.F.: Efficient capital markets: a review of theory and empirical work. J. Finance 25, 383–417 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fama, E.F.: Efficient capital markets: a review of theory and empirical work II. J. Finance 46, 1575–1618 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S.: The Nature and Significance of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. Institute for Advanced Study. Mimeo, Princeton (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G.: Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Verlag von Louis Nebert, Halle a. S (1879) (English edition: Concept script: a formal language of pure thought modelled upon that of arithmetic. In: van Heijenoort, J. (ed.) From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1967)

  • Frydman, R., Goldberg, M.D.: Imperfect Knowledge Economics: Exchange Rates and Risk. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frydman, R., Goldberg, M.D.: Macroeconomic theory for a world of imperfect knowledge. Cap. Soc. 3(3), 1–76 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frydman, R., Goldberg, M.D.: The imperfect knowledge imperative in modern macroeconomics and finance theory. In: Frydman, R., Phelps, E.S. (eds.) Rethinking Expectations: The Way Forward for Macroeconomics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K.: Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der “Principia Mathematica” und verwandter Systeme I, Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38 (1931) (English edition: On Formally Undecidable Propositions of “Principia Mathematica” and Related Systems I). In: Kurt Gödel (ed.) Collected Works, vol. I: Publications 1929–1936, pp. 144–195. Oxford University Press (1986)

  • Hausman, D.M.: The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1992)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D.M. (ed.): The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1994)

  • Heisenberg, W.K.: Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik. Zeitschrift für Physik, 43(3–4), 172–198 (1927) (English edition: On the perceptual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics. In John A. Wheeler and Wojciech Zurek (eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement, pp. 62–84. Princeton University Press, 1983)

  • Hicks, J.R.: Causality in Economics. Blackwell, Oxford (1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D.: Mathematische Probleme: Vortrag, gehalten auf dem internationalen Mathematiker-Kongreß zu Paris (1900) (English edition: Mathematical Problems: Lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris in 1900. http://www.mat.uc.pt/~delfos/hilbertprob.pdf)

  • Hofstadter, D.R.: Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. Basic Books, New York (1979)

  • Ingrao, B., Israel, G.: The Invisible Hand: Economic Equilibrium in the History of Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Tversky, A.: Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47, 263–291 (1979)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, N.: What is wrong with Economic Theory? Q. J. Econ. 89, 347–357 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kay, J.: The Map is not the Territory: An Essay on the State of Economics. Mimeo, New York (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan, London (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: The general theory of employment. Q. J. Econ. 51, 209–223 (1937)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: Collected Writings. Macmillan, London (1971–1989)

  • Kirman, A.: Complex Economics: Individual and Colletive Rationality. Routledge, Abingdon (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.H.: Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Houghton Mifflin, Boston (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.H.: The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays. Harper & Bros, New York (1935)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.H.: Freedom and Reform: Essays in Economics and Social Philosophy. Harper & Bros, New York (1947)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.H.: Laissez-Faire: Pro and Con. J. Polit. Econ. 75, 782–795 (1967)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.: Convention: A Philosophical Study. Harvard University Press (1969)

  • Lolli, G.: Thirty Years’ War (1900–1930): From Hilbert to Gödel. La guerra dei trent’anni, Da Hilbert a Gödel), Pisa, Ets (2011)

  • Lucas, R.E., Sargent, T.J.: Rational Expectations and Econometric Practice. Allen & Unwin, London (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lunghini, G.: Mathematical form and economic contents (Forma matematica e contenuto economico). http://cfs.unipv.it/scritti.htm (2002)

  • Marshall, A.: Principles of Economics. Macmillan, London (1920)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S.: On the definition of political economy and method of investigation proper to it (1836). In: Hausman, D.M. (ed.) The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1994)

  • Muth, J.F.: Rational expectations and the theory of price movements. Econometrica 29, 315–335 (1961)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odifreddi, P.: Göedel e Turing: The First Appearance of Computer and the Information Society (Göedel e Turing: La nascita del computer e la società dell’informazione). L’Espresso Publisher, Rome (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Parrinello, S.: Economic Language and Economic Facts (Linguaggio e realtà in economia). Esculapio, Bologna (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E.S.: The trouble with rational expectations and the problem of inflation stabilization. In: Frydman, R., Phelps, E.S. (eds.) Individual Forecasting and Aggregate Outcomes: Rational Expectations Examined. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E.S.: Structural Slumps: The Modern Equilibrium Theory of Unemployment, Interest and Assets. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E.S., Archibald, G.C., Alchian, A.A.: Microeconomic Foundations of Employment and Inflation Theory. Norton, New York (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigou, A.C.: The Economics of Welfare. Macmillan, London (1920)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigou, A.C.: Some aspects of welfare economics. Am. Econ. Rev. 41, 287–302 (1951)

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: A World of Propensities. Thoemmes Antiquarian Books, Bristol (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.: Two dogmas of empiricism. Philos. Rev. 60(1), 20–43 (1951)

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L.: An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. Macmillan, London (1932)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodrik, D.: Occupy the Classroom?, Project Syndicate. http://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/rodrik65/English (2011)

  • Russell, B.A.W.: A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz: With an Appendix of Leading Passages. Cambridge University Press (1900)

  • Sarkar, S.: The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals. Garland Pub, New York (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Simili, R. (ed.): Epistemology in Cambridge UK (L’epistemologia di Cambridge 1850–1950). il Mulino, Bologna (1987)

  • Simon, H.A.: Models of Bounded Rationality. Economic Analysis and Public Policy, vol. 1. MIT Press, Cambridge (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A., Egidi, M., Marris, R., Viale, R.: Economics, Bounded Rationality and the Cognitive Revolution. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  • Solow, R.M.: A contribution to the theory of economic growth. Q. J. Econ. 70(1), 65–94 (1956)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, I.: Seventeen Equations that Changed the World. Profile Books, London (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing A.M.: On Computable Numbers: With an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. In: Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, Ser. 2, vol. 42, 230–265; A correction, ibid., Ser. 2, vol. 43, 544–546 (1937)

  • von Hayek, F.A.: The use of knowledge in society. Am. Econ. Rev. 35, 519–530 (1945)

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hayek, F.A.: Individualism and Economic Order. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1948)

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hayek, F.A.: The Pretence of Knowledge, Nobel Lecture, 1974. In: New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and History of Ideas, University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1978)

  • Whitehead A.N., Russell B.: Principia Mathematica, vol. 3. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1910, 1912, 1913)

  • Wittgenstein L.J.J.: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, with an Introduction by Bertrand Russell. Harcourt, New York (1922)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giuseppe Garofalo.

Appendix: Ike models vs Reh models

Appendix: Ike models vs Reh models

Starting from Frydman and Goldberg (2008) we can directly compare Ike and Reh models on the basis of a basic supply and demand analysis. The equilibrium market price at a point in time is:

$$\begin{aligned} P_t =a_t +b_t X_t +c_t {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }, \end{aligned}$$

where:

  • \(X_{t}\) is a set of causal variables:Footnote 13

    $$\begin{aligned} X_t =\mu ^{X}+X_{t-1} +\varepsilon _t^X \end{aligned}$$
  • \({\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. } \) is an aggregate of market forecasts settled starting from a vector of causal variables that characterizes the union of information sets used by market participants:

    $$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. } =\alpha _t +\beta _t Z_t, \end{aligned}$$

    where \(Z_t =\mu ^{Z}+Z_{t-1} +\varepsilon _t^{Z}\)

Applying the Reh (the superscript “RE” denotes a Reh representation), \({\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{RE} =E(P_{t+1} \left| {X_t )} \right. \) and the market price at \(t +1\) is:

$$\begin{aligned} P_{t+1}^{\textit{RE}} =\frac{a(1-c)+b\mu ^{X}}{(1-c)^{2}}+\frac{b}{(1-c)}X_t +\varepsilon _{t+1}, \end{aligned}$$

where \(\varepsilon _{t+1} =\frac{b}{(1-c)}\varepsilon _{t+1}^X \). The average representative forecast of the price formed at \(t\) is:

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{RE}} =\frac{a(1-c)+b\mu ^{X}}{(1-c)^{2}}+\frac{b}{(1-c)}X_t \end{aligned}$$

The implication is that \(Z_t =X_t \).

If we assume a diversity of the individual forecasting strategies (e.g. type 1 and type 2 individuals), we have that:

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{RE}} =\omega {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^1 +(1-\omega ){\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^2 =\omega (\alpha ^{1}+\beta ^{1}X_t )+(1-\omega )(\alpha ^{2}+\beta ^{2}X_t ), \end{aligned}$$

where the weight \(0<\omega >1\) represents the importance of type 1 individuals in influencing the equilibrium price. Then, unless \(\omega =0\), the model presumes persistent forecasting errors.

The Ike (the superscript “IK” denotes Ike) representation of the aggregate of individual’s forecasts \({\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{IK}}\) is the aggregation of individual’s forecast that can change over time according to movements in the causal variables \((Z)\) or revisions of forecasting strategies (\(\beta \)), so that:Footnote 14

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{IK}} \longrightarrow P_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^i =\beta _t^i Z_t^i, \end{aligned}$$

where \(i\), in the context of asset, or currency (the last will be our reference point) market, can be seen, alternatively, as a bull or a bear strategy (we will adopt this hypothesis shortly).

Since the revisions and diversity of forecasting strategies characterize real world markets, we can write market price equation as:

$$\begin{aligned} P_t =P_t^{\textit{RE}} +c\left( {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{IK}} -{\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{\textit{RE}}\right) , \end{aligned}$$

where \(P_t^{\textit{RE}} \), in the context of currency markets, can be seen as the PPP exchange rate.

Now we can explain a total change in an individual’s forecast as:

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^i -{\hat{P}}_{t-1\left| t \right. }^i =D\!{\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^i +\varepsilon _t^{i}, \end{aligned}$$

where the trend change \(D\!{\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^i =\Delta \beta _t^i Z_t^i +\beta _{t-1}^i \mu ^{Z^{i}}(\Delta \beta _t^{i}\) shows the revisions of forecasting strategy, while \(\beta _{t-1}^i \mu ^{Z^{i}}\) is the baseline drift).

Ike recognizes conservatism constraints in revision of forecasting strategies, so that:

$$\begin{aligned} \left| {\Delta \beta _t^i Z_t^i } \right| <\left| {\beta _{t-1}^i \mu ^{Z^{i}}} \right| \quad \mathrm {and} \quad \left| {\Delta \beta _t^i \mu ^{Z^{i}}} \right| <\left| {\beta _{t-1}^i \mu ^{Z^{i}}} \right| \end{aligned}$$

How Frydman–Goldberg note, “economists sometimes recognize that changes in causal variables may lead to revisions of individual’s forecasting strategies. But, when they do, they rely on pre-existing rules, like Baye’s formula. By contrast, our Ike formulation recognizes that individuals do not endlessly obey pre-existing rules in deciding on when and how to alter their forecasting strategies. Indeed, the decision to revise one’s forecasting strategy depends on many factors, including prior forecasting success, economic and political developments, emotions, or ... the size of the departure of the exchange rate from PPP” (2008, p. 50).

Within the specified framework we can suppose markets populated by bulls and bears taking, respectively, long \((L)\) or short \((S)\) positions, with expected returns given by:

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{R}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^L&= {\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^L -P_{t} >0 \\ {\hat{R}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^S&= P_t -{\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^S >0, \end{aligned}$$

where \({\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^L =\beta _t^L Z_t^L \) and \({\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^S =\beta _t^S Z_t^S \) represent aggregates of the exchange rate forecasts of two types of individuals.

An individual’s expected loss from speculation can be written respectively as:

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{l}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{i,L}&= E_t^{i} \left[ R_{t+1}^L <0\left| {Z_t^i } \right. \right] <0 \\ {\hat{l}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{i,S}&= E_t^{i} \left[ R_{t+1}^S <0\left| {Z_t^i } \right. \right] <0, \end{aligned}$$

where \(E_t^i \Big [R_{t+1}^L <0\left| {Z_t^i } \right. \Big ]\) and \(E_t^i \Big [R_{t+1}^S >0\left| {Z_t^i } \right. \Big ]\) denote the expected value of the realizations on \(R_{t+1}^L \) and \(R_{t+1}^S \), given by \(R_{t+1}^L =P_{t+1} -P_t \) and \(R_{t+1}^S =P_t -P_{t+1} \)

Individual bull and bear radically revises her forecasting strategies if:

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{D{\hat{l}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{i,L} }{Dg{\hat{a}}p_t^{i,L} }<0 \\&\frac{D{\hat{l}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^{i,S} }{Dg{\hat{a}}p_t^{i,S} }>0, \end{aligned}$$

where \(g{\hat{a}}p_t^i ={\hat{P}}_{t\left| {t+1} \right. }^i -{\hat{P}}_t^{\textit{i,PPT}} \) while \({\hat{P}}_t^{\textit{i,PPP}} \) denotes an individual’s assessment at \(t\) of the PPP exchange rate.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Garofalo, G. Irreducible complexities: from Gödel and Turing to the paradigm of Imperfect Knowledge Economics. Qual Quant 48, 3463–3474 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11135-013-9967-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11135-013-9967-5

Keywords

Navigation