Skip to main content
Log in

Sabotage in team contests

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the contest literature, sabotage is defined as a deliberate and costly activity that damages the opponent’s likelihood of winning the contest. Most of the existing results suggest that, anticipating a possible sabotage, contestants would be discouraged from exerting high efforts. In this paper we investigate the act of sabotage in a team contest wherein team members exert costly efforts as a contribution to their team’s aggregate effort, which in turn determines the contest’s outcome. For the baseline model with no sabotage, there exists a corner equilibrium implying a free-rider problem in each team. As for the model with sabotage, our characterization of Nash equilibrium reveals two important results: (i) a unique interior equilibrium exists so that the free-rider problem no longer is a concern and (ii) the discouragement effect of sabotage vanishes for some players. On top of those conclusions, we investigate the team owner’s problems of prize allocation and team formation with the objective being to maximize his team’s winning probability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more real-life examples, see a recent survey by Chowdhury and Gürtler (2015).

  2. A result that is verified observationally by a number of studies (e.g., Garicano and Palacios-Huerta 2014; Harbring and Irlenbusch 2005, 2011; Vandegrift and Yavas 2010).

  3. Treating a group of attackers/defenders as a single decision-maker, we label them as a team member. The same is true for the alternative interpretations that follow.

  4. Sabotage activity is said to be directed if a player is facing multiple opponents and is able to choose the victim of his sabotage. Here we restrict the possible directions for sabotage, arguing that the attackers/defenders in a football team are facing the defenders/attackers in the opposing team. For the interested reader, we analyze the case of directed sabotage in Appendix 2 and characterize the conditions under which the model reduces to our original model with directionally restricted sabotage.

  5. Indeed, if one considers our baseline model in the context of public good provision, such results date back to Olson (1965).

  6. Following the war interpretation, the destruction of a rival’s weaponry or resources can be labeled as a sabotage act. Or, following the election interpretation, a possible sabotage activity would be negative campaigning.

  7. From another perspective, we study a team contest played on a small network with (i) four nodes representing the team members and (ii) three types of links representing their interactions (see Fig. 1). In particular, a1 has a friendship link with d1; a2 has a friendship link with d2; a1 and d1 have competition links with both a2 and d2; a1 has a sabotage link with d2; and d1 has a sabotage link with a2.

  8. There is another well-known solution to complete free riding in team contests, even when sabotage is not available. If players have strictly convex cost functions, then it is possible to construct an equilibrium in which both team members exert positive productive efforts (see Esteban and Ray 2001). Accordingly, it can be argued that the introduction of sabotage plays a role analogous to that played by a strictly convex cost function.

  9. An oversimplified model refers to a model that disregards the possibility of sabotage although the real-life scenario to be explained includes a sabotage act. Apparently, such an oversimplified model might make significantly different predictions.

  10. We thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing this point to our attention.

  11. Suppose that the effectiveness parameters could differ across teams and assume without loss of generality that \(\mu _1^d > \mu _2^d\). That assumption implies that team 1 cannot hire a defender with a sabotage cost lower than that of the defenders in team 2. This conclusion surely sounds odd. Here we simply assume that \(\mu ^j\) is a property of a player, but not a team.

  12. The setup eliminates the strategic interaction between team owners. Independent of what the owner of team \(-i\) does, the owner of team i would always choose the same values of effectiveness parameters for his team’s attackers and defenders.

  13. In the baseline model with no sabotage, the free riding result makes the team owner’s problems trivial, since the team owner would concentrate on the reward for the most motivated member of his team.

  14. Notice that if all winning prizes are multiplied by the same scalar, then the equilibrium values for \(E_1\) and \(E_2\) remain unchanged. Accordingly, for any quadruple of winning prizes, a scalar can be found above which the respective winning prizes lead to positive sabotage efforts for all players.

  15. Note that

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \left( \frac{f(x)}{f(x)+g(x)}\right) ' = \frac{f'(x)(f(x) + g(x)) - f(x)(f(x)'+g(x)')}{(f(x) + g(x))^2} = \frac{f'(x)g(x) - f(x) g'(x)}{(f(x) + g(x))^2}, \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$

    so that in order for this derivative to be equal to zero, it must be that

    $$\begin{aligned} f'(x)g(x) = f(x) g'(x). \end{aligned}$$
  16. We are referring to the football game or war interpretations here. If we consider the election interpretation, we would expect that \(\mu _1^{aa} < \mu _1^{da}\), since player a in team 1 is now closer to player a in team 2 than player d in team 1 is.

References

  • Amegashie, J. A. (2012). Productive versus destructive efforts in contests. European Journal of Political Economy, 28, 461–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baik, K. H. (1993). Effort levels in contests: The public-good prize case. Economics Letters, 41, 363–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baik, K. H. (2008). Contests with group-specific public-good prizes. Social Choice and Welfare, 30, 103–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baik, K. H., Kim, I. G., & Na, S. (2001). Bidding for a group-specific public-good prize. Journal of Public Economics, 82, 415–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balafoutas, L., Lindner, F., & Sutter, M. (2012). Sabotage in tournaments: Evidence from a natural experiment. Kyklos, 65, 425–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, A., & Chowdhury, S. M. (2017). The hidden perils of affirmative action: Sabotage in handicap contests. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 133, 273–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, K. P. (2003). Sabotage in promotion tournaments. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 19, 119–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chowdhury, S. M., & Gürtler, O. (2015). Sabotage in contests: A survey. Public Choice, 164, 135–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutscher, C., Frick, B., Gürtler, O., & Prinz, J. (2013). Sabotage in tournaments with heterogeneous contestants: Empirical evidence from the soccer pitch. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 115, 1138–1157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dye, R. A. (1984). The trouble with tournaments. Economic Inquiry, 22, 147–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2001). Collective action and the group-size paradox. American Political Science Review, 95, 663–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garicano, L., & Palacios-Huerta, I. (2014). Making the beautiful game a bit less beautiful. Beautiful game theory–how soccer can help economics (pp. 124–150). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gershkov, A., Li, J., & Schweinzer, P. (2009). Efficient tournaments within teams. The RAND Journal of Economics, 40, 103–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gürtler, O. (2008). On sabotage in collective tournaments. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 44, 383–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gürtler, O., & Münster, J. (2010). Sabotage in dynamic tournaments. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 46, 179–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbring, C., & Irlenbusch, B. (2005). Incentives in tournaments with endogenous prize selection. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 161, 636–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbring, C., & Irlenbusch, B. (2011). Sabotage in tournaments: Evidence from a laboratory experiment. Management Science, 57, 611–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbring, C., Irlenbusch, B., Kräkel, M., & Selten, R. (2007). Sabotage in corporate contests-an experimental analysis. International Journal of the Economics of Business, 14, 367–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmström, B. (1982). Moral hazard in teams. The Bell Journal of Economics, 13, 324–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Itoh, H. (1991). Incentives to help in multi-agent situations. Econometrica, 59, 611–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K. A. (2000). Sabotage in rent-seeking contests. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 16, 155–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazear, E. P. (1989). Pay equality and industrial politics. Journal of Political Economy, 97, 561–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAfee, R. P., & McMillan, J. (1991). Optimal contracts for teams. International Economic Review, 32, 561–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Münster, J. (2007). Selection tournaments, sabotage, and participation. Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 16, 943–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S. (1991). Collective rent dissipation. The Economic Journal, 101, 1522–1534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandegrift, D., & Yavas, A. (2010). An experimental test of sabotage in tournaments. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 166, 259–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vander Veen, T. D. (1995). Optimal contracts for teams: A note on the results of McAfee and McMillan. International Economic Review, 36, 1051–1056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the editor and an anonymous reviewer, as well as seminar participants at ADA University, Bilgi University, Bosphorus Workshop on Economic Design, and Koç University Winter Workshop in Economics. The usual disclaimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kerim Keskin.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Proof of Proposition 1

Given an aggregate effort \({\mathcal {E}}_2\) for team 2, the first-order condition with respect to \(e_1^a\) for player a in team 1 is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\gamma _1^a {\mathcal {E}}_2}{({\mathcal {E}}_1 + {\mathcal {E}}_2)^2} V_1^a - 1 = 0 . \end{aligned}$$

For player d in team 1, a symmetric first-order condition can be written as

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\gamma _1^d {\mathcal {E}}_2}{({\mathcal {E}}_1 + {\mathcal {E}}_2)^2} V_1^d - 1 = 0 . \end{aligned}$$

Accordingly, it must be that

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma _1^a V_1^a = \gamma _1^d V_1^d \end{aligned}$$
(1)

in the equilibrium, which is not necessarily true. That leads to a corner solution such that if the right-hand side exceeds the left-hand side, then only the attackers exert positive productive effort in the equilibrium, and vice versa. Considering a symmetric result for the other team, and under the assumption that \(\gamma _1^j V_1^j > \gamma _1^{j'} V_1^{j'}\) and \(\gamma _2^k V_2^k > \gamma _2^{k'} V_2^{k'}\), the respective equilibrium efforts are

$$\begin{aligned} e_1^j = \frac{\gamma _1^j \gamma _2^k \left( V_1^j\right)^2 V_2^k}{\left( \gamma _1^j V_1^j + \gamma _2^k V_2^k\right) ^2}, \quad e_1^{j'} = 0 , \\ e_2^k = \frac{\gamma _1^j \gamma _2^k V_1^j \left( V_2^k\right)^2}{\left( \gamma _1^j V_1^j + \gamma _2^k V_2^k\right) ^2}, \quad e_2^{k'} = 0. \end{aligned}$$

so that

$$\begin{aligned} {\mathcal {E}}^*_1 = \frac{\left( \gamma _1^j\right)^2 \gamma _2^k \left( V_1^j\right)^2 V_2^k}{\left( \gamma _1^j V_1^j + \gamma _2^k V_2^k\right) ^2}, \quad \hbox {and }\quad {\mathcal {E}}^*_2 = \frac{\gamma _1^j \left( \gamma _2^k\right)^2 V_1^j \left( V_2^k\right)^2}{\left( \gamma _1^j V_1^j + \gamma _2^k V_2^k\right) ^2} . \end{aligned}$$
(2)

Finally, for the sake of completeness, we must note that if Eq. (1) indeed holds for team \(i \in \{1,2\}\), then multiple equilibria exist such that both members of team i exert non-negative productive efforts reaching an aggregate effort of \({\mathcal {E}}_i^*\). \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 2

Consider the maximization problems for players d in team 1 and a in team 2. The corresponding first-order conditions can be written as

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial {U_1^d}}{\partial {e_1^d}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _1^d}}{1+{s_2^a}} \dfrac{E_2}{(E_1+E_2)^2}{V_1^d} - 1 =0 \end{aligned}$$
(3)
$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial {U_1^d}}{\partial {s_1^d}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _2^a}}{\left( 1+{s_1^d}\right) ^2} \dfrac{ {e_2^a}E_1}{(E_1+E_2)^2}{V_1^d} - {\mu _1^d} =0 \end{aligned}$$
(4)
$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial {U_2^a}}{\partial {e_2^a}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _2^a}}{1+{s_1^d}} \dfrac{E_1}{(E_1+E_2)^2}{V_2^a} - 1 =0 \end{aligned}$$
(5)
$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial {U_2^a}}{\partial {s_2^a}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _1^d}}{\left( 1+{s_2^a}\right) ^2} \dfrac{ {e_1^d}E_2}{(E_1+E_2)^2}{V_2^a} - {\mu _2^a} =0 \end{aligned}$$
(6)

From (3) we get

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{\gamma _1^d} E_2 {V_1^d}}{(E_1+E_2)^2} = 1+{s_2^a} ; \end{aligned}$$

and from (6) we get

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{\gamma _1^d} E_2 {V_2^a}}{(E_1+E_2)^2} = {\mu _2^a}\frac{\left( 1+{s_2^a}\right) ^2}{{e_1^d}} . \end{aligned}$$

Thus

$$\begin{aligned} {e_1^d} = \frac{{\mu _2^a}{\gamma _1^d} E_2 \left( {V_1^d}\right) ^2}{{V_2^a}(E_1+E_2)^2} . \end{aligned}$$

In a similar manner, we can write all productive and sabotage efforts in terms of each \(\gamma _i^j\), \(V_i^j\), \(\mu _i^j\), and \(E_i\). The values are

$$\begin{aligned} 1+{s_1^d}= & {} \frac{{\gamma _2^a} E_1 {V_2^a}}{(E_1+E_2)^2}, \quad 1+{s_1^a} = \frac{{\gamma _2^d} E_1 {V_2^d}}{(E_1+E_2)^2} , \end{aligned}$$
(7)
$$\begin{aligned} 1+{s_2^d}= & {} \frac{{\gamma _1^a} E_2 {V_1^a}}{(E_1+E_2)^2}, \quad 1+{s_2^a} = \frac{{\gamma _1^d} E_2 {V_1^d}}{(E_1+E_2)^2} , \end{aligned}$$
(8)
$$\begin{aligned} {e_1^d}= & {} \frac{{\mu _2^a}{\gamma _1^d} E_2 \left( {V_1^d}\right) ^2}{{V_2^a}(E_1+E_2)^2}, \quad {e_1^a} = \frac{{\mu _2^d}{\gamma _1^a} E_2 \left( {V_1^a}\right) ^2}{{V_2^d}(E_1+E_2)^2} , \end{aligned}$$
(9)
$$\begin{aligned} {e_2^d}= & {} \frac{{\mu _1^a}{\gamma _2^d} E_1 ({V_2^d})^2}{{V_1^a}(E_1+E_2)^2}, \quad {e_2^a} = \frac{{\mu _1^d}{\gamma _2^a} E_1 \left( {V_2^a}\right) ^2}{{V_1^d}(E_1+E_2)^2} . \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Notice that we also have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{e_2^a}}{(1+{s_1^d})} ={\mu _1^d}\frac{{V_2^a}}{{V_1^d}}; \end{aligned}$$

and by symmetry,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{e_1^a}}{\left( 1+{s_2^d}\right) } ={\mu _2^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} \hbox { ; }\frac{{e_2^d}}{\left( 1+{s_1^a}\right) } ={\mu _1^a}\frac{{V_2^d}}{{V_1^a}} \quad \hbox {and }\frac{{e_1^d}}{\left( 1+{s_2^a}\right) } ={\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} . \end{aligned}$$

Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} E^*_1 = {\gamma _1^d}\frac{{e_1^d}}{1+ {s_2^a}} + {\gamma _1^a}\frac{{e_1^a}}{1+ {s_2^d}} = {\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} + {\gamma _1^a}{\mu _2^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} E^*_2 = {\gamma _2^d}\frac{{e_2^d}}{1+ {s_1^a}} + {\gamma _2^a}\frac{{e_2^a}}{1+ {s_1^d}} = {\gamma _2^d} {\mu _1^a}\frac{{V_2^d}}{{V_1^a}} + {\gamma _2^a}{\mu _1^d}\frac{{V_2^a}}{{V_1^d}} . \end{aligned}$$

By replacing those \(E^*_1\) and \(E^*_2\) values into Eqs. (7)–(10), we can write the equilibrium values of all productive and sabotage efforts.

Finally, from Eqs. (7)–(10), we can derive the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of an interior equilibrium: Given positive aggregate efforts for both teams, an interior equilibrium exists if and only if for every player \(j \in \{a,d\}\) in team \(i \in \{1,2\}\), we have \(s_i^j > 0\), i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{\gamma _i^j} E_{-i} {V_i^j}}{(E_1+E_2)^2} > 1. \end{aligned}$$

And those inequalities are satisfied easily if all of the winning prizes are sufficiently large.Footnote 14 This completes the proof. \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 3

For given values of \(\gamma _i^j\) and \(\mu _i^j\) for every player \(j \in \{a,d\}\) in team \(i \in \{1,2\}\), the owner of team 1 aims to maximize

$$\begin{aligned} P_1(E_1, E_2) = \frac{E_1}{E_1+E_2} = \frac{{\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} + {\gamma _1^a}{\mu _2^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}}}{\left( {\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} + {\gamma _1^a}{\mu _2^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}}\right) + \left( {\gamma _2^d} {\mu _1^a}\frac{{V_2^d}}{{V_1^a}} + {\gamma _2^a}{\mu _1^d}\frac{{V_2^a}}{{V_1^d}}\right) } . \end{aligned}$$

The first-order condition for team 1 yieldsFootnote 15

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial E_1}{\partial {V_1^d}}E_2 = \frac{\partial E_2}{\partial {V_1^d}} E_1 . \end{aligned}$$

Now, considering that \({V_1^a}\) and \({V_1^d}\) are dependent variables, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \left( {\gamma _1^d}{\mu _2^a}\frac{1}{{V_2^a}} - {\gamma _1^a} {\mu _2^d} \frac{1}{{V_2^d}}\right) E_2 = \left( {\gamma _2^d}{\mu _1^a}\frac{{V_2^d}}{\left( {V_1^a}\right) ^2} - {\gamma _2^a} {\mu _1^d} \frac{{V_2^a}}{\left( {V_1^d}\right) ^2}\right) E_1 . \end{aligned}$$

Similarly, for team 2 we get

$$\begin{aligned} \left( {\gamma _2^d}{\mu _1^a}\frac{1}{{V_1^a}} - {\gamma _2^a} {\mu _1^d} \frac{1}{{V_1^d}}\right) E_1 = \left( {\gamma _1^d}{\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{\left( {V_2^a}\right) ^2} - {\gamma _1^a} {\mu _2^d} \frac{{V_1^a}}{\left( {V_2^d}\right) ^2}\right) E_2 . \end{aligned}$$

After arranging terms, we are left with

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ {\gamma _1^d}{\gamma _2^d}{\mu _1^a}{\mu _2^a}\left( {V_1^d}{V_2^d}\right) ^2 + {\gamma _1^a}{\gamma _2^a}{\mu _1^d}{\mu _2^d}\left( {V_1^a}{V_2^a}\right) ^2\right] \left( {V_1^d}{V_2^d} - {V_1^a}{V_2^a}\right) = 0 . \end{aligned}$$

Since the first term is positive, it must be that \({V_1^d}{V_2^d} = {V_1^a}{V_2^a}\). From this equation we find that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} = \frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} = \frac{{V_1^d} + {V_1^a}}{{V_2^d} + {V_2^a}} = \frac{V_1}{V_2} . \end{aligned}$$

Then, for the sake of expositional simplicity, we set

$$\begin{aligned} \rho _{1}^d ={\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}, \quad \rho _{2}^d = {\gamma _2^d} {\mu _1^a}, \quad \rho _{1}^a = {\gamma _1^a} {\mu _2^d}, \quad \hbox { and } \rho _{2}^a = {\gamma _2^a} {\mu _1^d} . \end{aligned}$$

Now we can write

$$\begin{aligned} E_1 = {\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} + {\gamma _1^a}{\mu _2^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} = \frac{V_1}{V_2} \left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} E_2 = {\gamma _2^d} {\mu _1^a}\frac{{V_2^d}}{{V_1^a}} + {\gamma _2^a}{\mu _1^d}\frac{{V_2^a}}{{V_1^d}} = \frac{V_2}{V_1} \left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Following some algebraic operations, the first-order condition for team 1 can be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \rho _{1}^d \frac{V_1}{V_2 {V_1^d}} - \rho _{1}^a \frac{V_1}{V_2 {V_1^a}}\right) \frac{V_2}{V_1}\left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) = \left( \rho _{2}^d \frac{V_2}{V_1 {V_1^a}} - \rho _{2}^a \frac{V_2}{V_1 {V_1^d}}\right) \frac{V_1}{V_2}\left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Canceling out all \(V_1\) and \(V_2\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\rho _{1}^d\left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) + \rho _{2}^a \left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) }{{V_1^d}}= \frac{\rho _{2}^d \left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) + \rho _{1}^a \left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) }{{V_1^a}} . \end{aligned}$$

From this equality we find

$$\begin{aligned} {V_1^d} = \frac{V_1 \left[ \rho _{1}^d \left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) + \rho _{2}^a \left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) \right] }{2\left( \rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a\right) \left( \rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a\right) } = \frac{V_1}{2}\left( \frac{\rho _{1}^d}{\rho _{1}^d + \rho _{1}^a} + \frac{ \rho _{2}^a }{\rho _{2}^d + \rho _{2}^a}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Finally, returning back to the standard notation, we have

$$\begin{aligned} {V_1^{d*}} = \frac{V_1}{2}\left( \frac{{\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a}}{{\gamma _1^d} {\mu _2^a} + {\gamma _1^a} {\mu _2^d}} + \frac{ {\gamma _2^a} {\mu _1^d} }{{\gamma _2^d} {\mu _1^a} + {\gamma _2^a} {\mu _1^d} }\right) . \end{aligned}$$

The optimal share for the other player is \(V_1^{a*} = V_1 - V_1^{d*}\). \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 4

Now that the strategic interaction is absent, the analysis turns out to be much simpler. The first-order condition with respect to \(\gamma _1^d\) is

$$\begin{aligned} {\mu ^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} + {\mu ^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} \frac{\partial \gamma _1^a}{\partial \gamma _1^d} = 0 . \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, from the derivative of the budget constraint, it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha \left( \gamma _1^a\right) ^{\alpha -1}\frac{\partial \gamma _1^a}{\partial \gamma _1^d} + \alpha \left( \gamma _1^d\right) ^{\alpha -1} = 0 \end{aligned}$$

which implies

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \gamma _1^a}{\partial \gamma _1^d} = -\,\left( \frac{\gamma _1^d}{\gamma _1^a}\right) ^{\alpha -1} . \end{aligned}$$

Using this information in the first-order condition above, we have

$$\begin{aligned} {\mu ^a}\frac{{V_1^d}}{{V_2^a}} - {\mu ^d}\frac{{V_1^a}}{{V_2^d}} \left( \frac{\gamma _1^d}{\gamma _1^a}\right) ^{\alpha -1} = 0 \end{aligned}$$

so that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\gamma _1^d}{\gamma _1^a} = \left( \frac{{\mu ^a}{V_1^d}{V_2^d}}{\mu ^d{V_2^a}{V_1^a}} \right) ^{\frac{1}{\alpha -1}} . \end{aligned}$$

Then putting this finding into the budget constraint, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma _1^{a*} = \left( \dfrac{\Gamma _1}{1 + \left( \dfrac{{\mu ^a}{V_1^d}{V_2^d}}{\mu ^d{V_2^a}{V_1^a}} \right) ^{\frac{\alpha }{\alpha -1}}}\right) ^\frac{1}{\alpha } \quad \hbox {and }\quad \gamma _1^{d*} = \left( \dfrac{\Gamma _1}{1 + \left( \dfrac{\mu ^d{V_2^a}{V_1^a}}{{\mu ^a}{V_1^d}{V_2^d}} \right) ^{\frac{\alpha }{\alpha -1}}}\right) ^\frac{1}{\alpha } . \end{aligned}$$

\(\square\)

Appendix 2

1.1 The alternative model with restricted sabotage

In this paper, we have considered directionally restricted sabotage allowing each member of a team to sabotage only a particular member of the opposing team. Here we relax that assumption and analyze the case of directed sabotage: each team member can sabotage any member of the opposing team. Similar to our original model, \(e_i^j\) denotes the productive effort exerted by player \(j\in \{a,d\}\) in team \(i\in \{1,2\}\). As for the sabotage efforts, we need a new notation including the origin and the destination of sabotage. Let \(s_i^{jk}\) denote the sabotage made by player \(j \in \{a,d\}\) in team \(i \in \{1,2\}\) against player \(k \in \{a,d\}\) in the opposing team. Also let \(\mu _i^{jk}\) denote the corresponding marginal cost of such sabotage activity.

Then, we can write the respective aggregate effort functions as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} E_1 = \frac{\gamma _1^a}{1+s_2^{aa}+s_2^{da}}e_1^a + \frac{\gamma _1^d}{1+s_2^{ad}+s_2^{dd}}e_1^d \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} E_2 = \frac{\gamma _2^a}{1+s_1^{aa}+s_1^{da}}e_2^a + \frac{\gamma _2^d}{1+s_1^{ad}+s_1^{dd}}e_2^d . \end{aligned}$$

Assuming that

$$\begin{aligned} C_i^j\left( e_i^j,s_i^{ja},s_i^{jd}\right) = e_i^j + \mu _i^{ja}s_i^{ja} + \mu _i^{jd}s_i^{jd}, \end{aligned}$$

we say that player \(j\in \{a,d\}\) in team \(i\in \{1,2\}\) maximizes

$$\begin{aligned} U_i^j \left( \left( e_i^j,s_i^{ja},s_i^{jd}\right) , \cdot \right) = \frac{E_i}{E_1+E_2}V_i^j -e_i^j - \mu _i^{ja}s_i^{ja} - \mu _i^{jd}s_i^{jd} . \end{aligned}$$

Utilizing the first-order conditions with respect to \(s_1^{aa}\) and \(s_1^{da}\), we get

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {U_1^a}}{\partial {s_1^{aa}}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _2^a}}{\left( 1+{s_1^{da} + s_1^{aa}}\right) ^2} \dfrac{e_2^a E_1}{\left( E_1+E_2\right) ^2}{V_1^a} - \mu _1^{aa} =0 \\ \frac{\partial {U_1^d}}{\partial {s_1^{da}}}&= \dfrac{{\gamma _2^a}}{\left( 1+{s_1^{da} + s_1^{aa}}\right) ^2} \dfrac{e_2^a E_1}{\left( E_1+E_2\right) ^2}{V_1^d} - \mu _1^{da} =0 . \end{aligned}$$

In order for these first-order conditions to be satisfied simultaneously, it must be that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{V_1^a}{\mu _1^{aa}} = \frac{V_1^d}{\mu _1^{da}}. \end{aligned}$$

Otherwise, we must have a corner solution. To put it differently, unless the last equality is satisfied, directionally restricted sabotage would be observed in the equilibrium. Below we elaborate further on that issue.

Note that if any of the derivatives with respect to \(s_1^{aa}\) and \(s_1^{da}\) are positive, then a marginal increment in the corresponding variable would be a possible deviation. Therefore, none can be positive at an equilibrium. The result implies that if one of the first-order conditions is satisfied, then the derivative with respect to the other variable should be negative, which corresponds to a corner solution for that variable. For more concrete arguments, assume without loss of generality that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{V_1^a}{\mu _1^{aa}} < \frac{V_1^d}{\mu _1^{da}}. \end{aligned}$$

If the former first-order condition is satisfied, then the derivative with respect to \(s_1^{da}\) would be positive. That cannot happen in equilibrium. Then, it must be that the latter first-order condition is satisfied, meaning that a corner solution exists for \(s_1^{aa}\), which is \(s_1^{aa}=0\).

Finally, given our model’s interpretation, it is reasonable to assume that \(\mu _1^{aa} > \mu _1^{da}\). That is because the defenders in team 1 are located closer to the attackers in team 2 than the attackers in team 1, so that if the attackers in team 2 are to be sabotaged, the defenders in team 1 should have a lower cost than the attackers in team 1.Footnote 16 Accordingly, for a wide range of \(V_1^a\), \(V_1^d\), \(V_2^a\), and \(V_2^d\) values, the current model would reduce to our original model with directionally restricted sabotage in the equilibrium.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Doğan, S., Keskin, K. & Sağlam, Ç. Sabotage in team contests. Public Choice 180, 383–405 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00643-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00643-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation