Skip to main content
Log in

A new defense of trope content view of experience

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The idea that what we perceive are tropes (abstract particulars) is anything but new. In fact, it was one of the reasons why the ontology of tropes was postulated in the first place. Still, the claim that we perceive tropes is invariably and purely based on pre-philosophical intuitions or, indirectly, either as a supporting argument for the advantages of content view when compared to the relational view of experience, or as a supporting argument in favor of the irreducible subjective character of experience. In this paper, I take the content view for granted and argue in favor of what is herein referred to as the trope-content view of experience. My defense is a case of inference to the best explanation. The trope-content view can meet all reasonable desiderata on the experience and its content without assuming gaps or making the ad hoc assumption that there are different layers of content, or so shall I argue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Regarding the advantages of the content view, see Nanny (2016). Regarding the irreducible subjective character of experience, qualia, see Bensusan amd Carvalho (2011). There are two fundamentally different ways of conceiving perceptual experience. The first one is this: experience has content. When I see a yellow cube straight ahead, I represent the world as being a certain way, that is, my perceptual states have conditions of satisfactions (see Searle 1983). When there is a match between how the world is and the way that our experiences reflect it, the content is veridical; on the other hand, when there is a mismatch, the content is falsidical. According to Campbell, we may call this “the content view” of perceptual experience (See Campbell 2002). Different versions of the “content view” have become popular since the seminal works of Anscombe (1965), Armstrong (1968) and Dretske (1969). The second view is the following: experience is a matter of putting the agent in contact with particulars. In accordance with Campbell, we may label this the “relational view” (see Campbell 2002). Versions of this view were popular amongst the early twentieth-century Oxford Realists, such as Russell (see 1912), but the recent work of Campbell, Johnston, Brewer, Fish, and Martin have brought the proposal back into discussion (See Johnston 2004; Brewer 2006; Fish 2009; Martin 2002; Travis 2004). Martin calls his position “naïve realism” (See Martin 2002); while Brewer calls his the “object view” (See Brewer 2006). However, I prefer Campbell’s label: the “relational view” (See Campbell 2002). In this paper, I take the content view for granted, without assuming the onus of arguing for it.

  2. See Searle (1983, p. 63).

  3. See Schellenberg (2010).

  4. See Schellenberg (2010).

  5. See Tye (2009, pp. 78–80).

  6. As Tye puts it: “intuitively, I misperceive that cube. My experience misrepresents it” (2009, p. 80. Original emphasis).

  7. That is what Lewis has call “veridical hallucinations”. See Lewis (1980). I have used this famous scenario at least twice: Pereira (2016, 2018).

  8. See Tye (2009).

  9. See Schellenberg (2010).

  10. See Tye (2014).

  11. See Mulligan et al. (1984) and Lowe (1998).

  12. See Nanay (2012).

  13. See Grice (1961).

  14. See Davies (1992, p. 26).

  15. See McGinn (1982).

  16. This experiment was proposed by Tye (2009, p. 79). Recently Schellenberg has presented the same experiment a little modified. See Schellenberg (2016).

    However, in my paper of 2012 (Pereira 2012), I show how a General content view could circumvent this objection by assuming that the general content is relativistic, namely a complex property that is true or false of particular with which we are acquainted rather then represent.

  17. See Tye (2009, pp. 79–80).

  18. That is Searle’s main mistake in (1983). See Bach (2007).

  19. See Campbell (1990), Bacon (1995) and Schaffer (2001).

  20. See Campbell (1990).

  21. See Bacon (1995).

  22. See footnote 20.

  23. See Campbell (1981, p. 481).

  24. Mulligan et al (1984, p. 300).

  25. See Rodriguez-Pereyra (2002, pp. 93–95). Siegel gives a very similar argument in (2005, 2009). See also Nanay (2012).

  26. See Tye (2009, p. 83).

  27. See Tye (2009, p. 83).

  28. See Searle (1983).

  29. See Tye (2009) and Schellenberg (2010).

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1965). The intentionality of sensation: A grammatical feature. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy: Second series. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2007). Searle against the world. How can experiences find their objects? In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), John Searle’s philosophy of language: Force, meaning, and thought (pp. 64–78). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, J. (1995). Universals and property instances. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bensusan, H. & Carvalho, E. (2011). Qualia qua qualitons: Mental qualities as abstract particulars. Acta Analytica, 26(2), 155–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, K. (1981). The metaphysics of abstract particulars. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 6, 477–488 (Reprinted in: D. H. Mellor & A. Oliver (Eds.) (1997), Properties (pp. 125–139). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Campbell, K. (1990). Abstract particulars. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (1992). Perceptual content and local supervenience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 92, 21–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehring, D. (1997). Causation and persistence: A theory of causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, 35, 121–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2004). The obscure object of hallucination. Philosophical Studies, 120, 113–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2004). Trope theory and the metaphysics of appearances. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41(1), 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). Veridical hallucination and prosthetic vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, 239–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1998). Possibility of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002). Particular thoughts and singular thought. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 51, 173–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1982). The character of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K., Barry, S., & Peter, S. (1984). Truth makers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 44, 278–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2012). An action-oriented perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 23, 321–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, R. (2012). The existentialist view (on the content of experience) being defended. Dois Pontos, 9(2), 63–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, R. (2016). Combining the representational and the relational view. Philosophical Studies, 173(12), 3255–3269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, R. (2018). The singular relational plus relativistic content view. Dialogue, 57(1), 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance nominalism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2001). The individuation of tropes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79, 247–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2010). Particularity and phenomenology of perceptual experience. Philosophical Studies, 149, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2016). Perceptual particularity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92(2), n/a–n/a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2005). The phenomenology of efficacy. Philosophical Topics, 33, 65–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2009). The visual experience of causation. Philosophical Quarterly, 59, 519–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2004). Silence of the senses. Mind, 113, 57–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited: Materialism without phenomenal concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2014). Transparency, qualia realism and representationalism. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Horácio de Sá Pereira.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

de Sá Pereira, R.H. A new defense of trope content view of experience. Philos Stud 176, 1757–1768 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1089-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1089-4

Keywords

Navigation