Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 5, pp 1183–1205 | Cite as

Definite descriptions and the alleged east–west variation in judgments about reference

  • Yu Izumi
  • Masashi Kasaki
  • Yan Zhou
  • Sobei Oda
Article

Abstract

Machery et al. (2004) presented data suggesting the existence of cross-cultural variation in judgments about the reference of proper names. In this paper, we examine a previously overlooked confound in the subsequent studies that attempt to replicate the results of Machery et al. (2004) using East Asian languages. Machery et al. (2010, 2015) and Sytsma et al. (2015) claim that they have successfully replicated the original finding with probes written in Chinese and Japanese, respectively. These studies, however, crucially rely on uses of articleless, ‘bare noun phrases’ in Chinese and Japanese, which according to the linguistic literature are known to be multiply ambiguous. We argue that it becomes questionable whether the extant studies using East Asian languages revealed genuine cross-cultural variation when the probes are reevaluated based on a proper linguistic understanding of Chinese and Japanese bare noun phrases and English definite descriptions. We also present two experiments on native Japanese speakers that controlled the use of ambiguous bare noun phrases, the results of which suggest that the judgments of Japanese speakers concerning the reference of proper names may not diverge from those of English speakers.

Keywords

Experimental philosophy Cross-cultural semantics Proper names Definite descriptions Articleless noun phrases 

Notes

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank James Beebe, Kent Erickson, Edouard Machery, Alex Rausch, Takashi Yagisawa, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on earlier drafts. We are also grateful to the audiences at the 2015 Japan Forum for Young Philosophers, the 2015 Buffalo Annual Experimental Philosophy Conference, the 2016 Central APA Meeting, Queen’s University Belfast, and Soochow University. This work was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grants-in-Aid for Scientific Research (26770006) and for JSPS Fellows (15J06699).

References

  1. Beebe, J. R., & Undercoffer, R. J. (2016). Individual and cross-cultural differences in semantic intuitions: New experimental findings. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 16(3–4), 322–357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Cheng, L. L.-S., & Sybesma, R. (1999). Bare and not-so-bare nouns and the structure of NP. Linguistic Inquiry, 30(4), 509–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Chierchia, G. (1998). Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language Semantics, 6(4), 339–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Colaço, D. & Machery, E. (2016). The intuitive is a red herring. Inquiry.Google Scholar
  5. Deutsch, M. (2009). Experimental philosophy and the theory of reference. Mind & Language, 24(4), 445–466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Deutsch, M. (2010). Intuitions, counter-examples, and experimental philosophy. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 447–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Deutsch, M. (2015). The myth of the intuitive: Experimental philosophy and philosophical method. A bradford book. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Devitt, M. (2011). Experimental semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(2), 418–435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Elbourne, P. D. (2013). Definite descriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hawkins, J. A. (1978). Definiteness and indefiniteness: a study in reference and grammaticality production. New Jersey: Atlantic Highlands.Google Scholar
  11. Hoji, H., Kinsui, S., Takubo, Y., & Ueyama, A. (2003). The demonstratives in modern Japanese. In A. hui, Y. Li, & A. Simpson (Eds.), Functional structure(s), form and interpretation: perspectives from east Asian languages (pp. 97–128). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  12. Ichikawa, J., Maitra, I., & Weatherson, B. (2012). In defense of a Kripkean dogma. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(1), 56–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Izumi, Y. (2011). Interpreting bare nouns: Type-shifting vs. silent heads. In The Proceedings of the 21st Semantics and Linguistics Theory, (pp. 481–494).Google Scholar
  14. Izumi, Y. (2012). The Semantics of Proper Names and Other Bare Nominals. PhD thesis, University of Maryland, College Park, MD.Google Scholar
  15. Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Kuno, S. (1973). The structure of the Japanese language. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Lam, B. (2010). Are Cantonese speakers really descriptivists?: Revisiting cross-cultural semantics. Cognition, 115(2), 320–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Ludwig, K. (2007). The epistemology of thought experiments: first person versus third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 128–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Machery, E. (2011). Variation in intuitions about reference and ontological disagreement. In S. D. Hales (Ed.), A companion to relativism (pp. 118–136). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Machery, E. (2012). Expertise and intuitions about reference. Theoria, 72(3), 37–54.Google Scholar
  21. Machery, E. (2014). What is the significance of the demographic variation in semantic intuitions? In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy (pp. 3–16). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  22. Machery, E., Deutsch, M., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., Sytsma, J., & Stich, S. (2010). Semantic intuitions: Reply to Lam. Cognition, 117(3), 363–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92(3), B1–B12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2013). If folk intuitions vary, then what? Philos Phenomenol Res, 86(3), 618–635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Machery, E., Olivola, C. Y., & Blanc, M. D. (2009). Linguistic and metalinguistic intuitions in the philosophy of language. Analysis, 69(4), 689–694.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Machery, E., & Stich, S. (2012). The role of experiment in the philosophy of language. In G. Russell & D. G. Fara (Eds.), The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 495–512). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  27. Machery, E., Sytsma, J., & Deutsch, M. (2015). Speaker’s reference and cross-cultural semantics. In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference (pp. 62–76). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Martí, G. (2009). Against semantic multi-culturalism. Analysis, 69(1), 42–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Martí, G. (2012). Empirical data and the theory of reference. In W. P. Kabasenche, M. O’Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Reference and referring: Topics in contemporary philosophy (pp. 63–82). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Sung, C. C. M. (2015). Hong Kong English: Linguistic and sociolinguistic perspectives. Language and Linguistics Compass, 9(6), 256–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2011). A new perspective concerning experiments on semanitic intuitions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(2), 315–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Sytsma, J., Livengood, J., Sato, R., & Oguchi, M. (2015). Reference in the land of the rising sun: A cross-cultural study on the reference of proper names. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(2), 212–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Anthropology and PhilosophyNanzan UniversityNagoya-shiJapan
  2. 2.Institute of Liberal Arts and SciencesNagoya UniversityNagoya-shiJapan
  3. 3.Division of EconomicsKyoto Sangyo DaigakuKyoto-shiJapan

Personalised recommendations