Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 174, Issue 8, pp 2083–2103 | Cite as

Bootstrapping and dogmatism

  • Tim Butzer
Article
  • 254 Downloads

Abstract

Dogmatists claim that having a perceptual experience as of p can provide one with immediate and defeasible warrant to believe that p. A persistent complaint against this position is that it sanctions an intuitively illicit form of reasoning: bootstrapping. I argue that dogmatism has no such commitments. Dogmatism is compatible with a principle that disallows the final non-deductive inference in the bootstrapping procedure. However, some authors have maintained that such strategy is doomed to failure because earlier stages of in the bootstrapping inference are already problematic. I argue that insofar as these inferences appear problematic, the dogmatist is not committed to sanctioning them. I conclude that the bootstrapping argument presents no significant objection to the claim that perceptual experiences can provide immediate and defeasible warrant to believe their contents.

Keywords

Epistemology Dogmatism Bootstrapping Perception Warrant 

Notes

Acknowledgments

There are many people who contributed to the development of this paper. I would like to thank Kevin Falvey and Aaron Zimmerman for reviewing previous drafts of this paper and providing many helpful comments. A special thanks to Michael Rescorla both for providing useful comments on earlier drafts, and during the late review stages of the paper. Thanks to Alex Bundy, Phil Atkins and Josh May for helpful discussions on these and related topics through the years. The original idea for this paper was conceived while I attended a seminar taught by Tony Brueckner on the bootstrapping argument. He was the first sounding board for the argument I present here, as he was for so many of my ideas (good and bad). He was a patient mentor, a clear and deeply honest thinker, and good friend. I miss him dearly.

References

  1. Alston, W. P. (1980). Level-confusions in epistemology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5(1), 135–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Audi, R. (1993). The structure of justification. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(3), 503–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cohen, S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 309–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohen, S. (2005). Why basic knowledge is easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 417–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cohen, S. (2010). Bootstrapping, defeasible reasoning, and a priori justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 141–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Fumerton, R. A. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  8. Goldman, A. I. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–25). Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  9. Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  11. Huemer, M. (2007). Compassionate phenomenal conservatism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(1), 30–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Markie, P. J. (2005a). Easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 406–416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Markie, P. J. (2005b). The mystery of direct perceptual justification. Philosophical Studies, 126(3), 347–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Moretti, L. (2015). In defence of dogmatism. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 261–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Peacocke, C. (2004a). Explaining perceptual entitlement. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge (pp. 441–480). Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  16. Peacocke, C. (2004b). The realm of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34(4), 517–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Rescorla, M. (2009). Epistemic and dialectical regress. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87(1), 43–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Van Cleve, J. (2003). Is knowledge easy—Or impossible? Externalism as the only alternative to skepticism. In S. Luper (Ed.), The Skeptics: Contemporary Essays. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  22. Vogel, J. (2000). Reliabilism leveled. Journal of Philosophy, 97(11), 602–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Weisberg, J. (2010). Bootstrapping in general. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 525–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. White, R. (2006). Problems for dogmatism. Philosophical Studies, 131(3), 525–557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Wright, C. (2007). The perils of dogmatism. In S. Nuccetelli & G. Seay (Eds.), Themes from G. E. Moore: New essays in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of AlabamaTuscaloosaUSA

Personalised recommendations