Skip to main content
Log in

Learning experiences and the value of knowledge

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Generalized probabilistic learning takes place in a black-box where present probabilities lead to future probabilities by way of a hidden learning process. The idea that generalized learning can be partially characterized by saying that it doesn’t foreseeably lead to harmful decisions is explored. It is shown that a martingale principle follows for finite probability spaces.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Savage (1954) also considers a version of this result. There is a note by F. P. Ramsey that anticipates the theorem (published as Ramsey 1990; see also Skyrms 1990 on this and on Good’s argument).

  2. The arguments presented here do not hold generally in infinite probability spaces if the probability measure is not countably additive (Kadane et al. 1996, 2008). Many scholars—de Finetti (1974) first and foremost among them—think that countable additivity should not be thought of as a coherence requirement. See Seidenfeld (2001) for a recent overview of reasons to take finite additivity as basic. See also Zabell (2002) and references therein on finitely additive martingale theory, which would be relevant for an extension of our results to more general situations.

  3. If the utilities don’t depend on the outcomes of the experiment, the terms here reduce to the earlier ones.

  4. Graves (1989) presents a generalization for probability kinematics.

  5. That each posterior p f is a probability function means that you expect to be statically coherent.

  6. That’s why it’s called (M) here and in Skyrms (1990).

  7. See Myrvold (2012) for a similar treatment with epistemic utility functions.

  8. More formally, suppose that there are n · m intervals around zero where m is the number of states. For i = 1,…, n, j = 1,…, m let u ij be an arbitrary number in the ijth interval. We assume that for all u ij there are acts A 1,…, A n such that u(A i &S j ) = u ij .

  9. It follows that this issue does not arise in Skyrms’ value of knowledge theorem. If the martingale principle is assumed to hold, then p f (S) = p(S|p f ) = 0 if p f is not the posterior in state S.

References

  • de Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of probability (Vol. 1). London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, M. (1983). The prevision of a prevision. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 78, 817–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1967). On the principle of total evidence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 17, 319–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graves, P. (1989). The total evidence principle for probability kinematics. Philosophy of Science, 56, 317–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huttegger, S. M. (2013). In defense of reflection. Philosophy of Science, 80, 413–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1965). The logic of decision. New York: McGraw-Hill. 3rd Revised edition, 1983. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1988). Conditioning, kinematics, and exchangeability. In B. Skyrms & W. L. Harper (Eds.) Causation, chance, and credence (Vol. 1, pp. 221–255). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1992). Probability and the art of judgement. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J. B., Schervish M. J., & Seidenfeld, T. (1996). Reasoning to a foregone conclusion. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 91, 1228–1236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J. B., Schervish, M., & Seidenfeld, T. (2008). Is ignorance bliss? The Journal of Philosophy, 105, 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myrvold, W. C. (2012). Epistemic values and the value of learning. Synthese, 187, 547–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1990). Weight or the value of knowledge. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 41, 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidenfeld, T. (2001). Remarks on the theory of conditional probability: Some issues of finite versus countable additivity. In V. F. Hendricks (Ed.), Probability theory (pp. 167–178). Amsterdam: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1990). The dynamics of rational deliberation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1997). The structure of radical probabilism. Erkenntnis, 45, 285–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1984). Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1995). Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the Sirens. Philosophical Studies, 77, 7–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zabell, S. L. (2002). It all adds up: The dynamic coherence of radical probabilism. Philosophy of Science, 69, 98–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simon M. Huttegger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Huttegger, S.M. Learning experiences and the value of knowledge. Philos Stud 171, 279–288 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0267-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0267-7

Keywords

Navigation