Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 158, Issue 2, pp 361–376 | Cite as

Absence of action

  • Randolph Clarke
Article

When I raise my arm, my raising my arm is an event. When I stop at the store and buy milk, my doing so is a process. When I omit to raise my arm or to stop and buy milk, what, if anything, is my not doing these things? What, in general, are omissions to act?

Sometimes when someone refrains from doing a certain thing, the agent performs an action of preventing himself from so acting. A policeman might hold his arm at his side to keep from shooting a fleeing suspect.1 But in many cases of omission there’s no such action. When I forget to stop and buy milk, my omission seems to be, in the first place, an absence, the absence of an action by me of buying milk.2 But what is an absence of an action?

Many things are absent from the world—many objects (unicorns), many states (perfect virtue), and many events (a World Series triumph by the Cubs in the last hundred years). If these things existed, they would be entities of various sorts. Are the absences of these things beings of some kind? If...

Keywords

Causal Relation Causal Effect Causal Power Negative State Genuine Property 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments on earlier versions of the paper, I want to thank Kent Bach, Mark Balaguer, Sara Bernstein, John Heil, Stephen Kearns, Al Mele, Achille Varzi, and the audience at the 2011 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference.

References

  1. Armstrong, D. M. (1978). Universals and scientific realism, Volume 2: A theory of universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. M. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Beall, J. C. (2000). On truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 264–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Beebee, H. (2004). Causing and nothingness. In J. Collins, N. Hal, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 291–308). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Brand, Myles. (1971). The language of not doing. American Philosophical Quarterly, 8, 45–53.Google Scholar
  7. Brownstein, D. (1973). Negative exemplification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 10, 43–50.Google Scholar
  8. Cheyne, C., & Pigden, C. (2006). Negative truths from positive facts. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 249–265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Clarke, R. (2010). Intentional omissions. Noûs, 44, 158–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Clarke, R. (2011). Omissions, responsibility, and symmetry. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 594–624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clarke, R. (in press). What is an omission? Philosophical Issues.Google Scholar
  12. Dodd, J. (2007). Negative truths and truthmaker principles. Synthese, 156, 383–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dowe, P. (2010). Proportionality and omissions. Analysis, 70, 446–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hochberg, H. (1969). Negation and generality. Noûs, 3, 325–343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kukso, B. (2006). The reality of absences. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 21–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lewis, D. (1992). Critical notice of D. M. Armstrong’s ‘A combinatorial theory of possibility’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 211–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Lewis, D. (2004). Void and object. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 277–290). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Martin, C. B. (1996). How it is: Entities, absences and voids. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 57–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A dilemma. Philosophical Studies, 123, 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Mele, A. R. (1997). Agency and mental action. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 231–249.Google Scholar
  23. Mellor, D. H. (1995). The facts of causation. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Mellor, D. H. (2004). For facts as causes and effects. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 309–323). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Priest, G. (2000). Truth and contradiction. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 305–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Schaffer, J. (2004). Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 197–216). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  27. Thomson, J. J. (2003). Causation: Omissions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 81–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Varzi, A. C. (2006). The talk I was supposed to give…. In A. Bottani & R. Davies (Eds.), Modes of existence: Papers in ontology and philosophical logic (pp. 131–151). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
  29. Weinryb, E. (1980). Omissions and responsibility. Philosophical Quarterly, 30, 1–18.Google Scholar
  30. Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Yablo, S. (1997). Wide causation. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 251–281.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Florida State UniversityTallahasseeUSA

Personalised recommendations