Philosophical Studies

, Volume 146, Issue 1, pp 29–48 | Cite as

Restricting factiveness



In discussions of Fitch’s paradox, it is usually assumed without further argument that knowledge is factive, that if a subject knows that p, then p is true. It is argued that this common assumption is not as well-founded as it should be, and that there in fact are certain reasons to be suspicious of the unrestricted version of the factiveness claim. There are two kinds of reason for this suspicion. One is that unrestricted factiveness leads to paradoxes and unexpected results, the other is that the usual arguments for factiveness are not as compelling as is commonly thought. There may in fact be some kinds of contexts, where factiveness doesn’t hold for knowledge—the usual arguments for factiveness don’t suffice to support the claim that knowledge is unrestrictedly factive. Perhaps all that can be shown is that knowledge is at times factive, or that it is default factive, as it were: this doesn’t show that there can’t be counterexamples, however. Certain aspects of knowledge without unrestricted factiveness are examined briefly.


Knowledge Factiveness Knower paradox Fitch’s knowability paradox 



Research for this paper was supported by a grant from the Swedish Science Council. An ancestor of this paper was presented at Peter Pagin’s Philosophy of language seminar at Stockholm University, and I would like to thank the participants at that seminar for valuable comments. Joe Salerno and an anonymous referee also provided valuable comments on an earlier version.


  1. Anderson, C. A. (1983). The paradox of the Knower. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 338–355.Google Scholar
  2. Ayer, A. (1973). On a supposed antinomy. Mind, 82 125–126.Google Scholar
  3. Beall, J. C. (2000). Fitch’s proof, verificationism, and the Knower paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 241–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brogaard, B., & Salerno, J. Fitch’s paradox of knowability. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  5. Church, A. (1945). First anonymous referee report on Fitch’s ‘A definition of value’. in Salerno (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  6. Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Edgington, D. (1985). The paradox of knowability. Mind, 94, 557–568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Kvanvig, J. (2006). The knowability paradox. Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  10. Mackie, J. L. (1980). Truth and knowability. Analysis, 40, 90–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Maudlin, T. (2004). Truth and paradox. Solving the riddles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. McGee, V. (1985). A counterexample to modus ponens. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 462–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Prior, A. (1960). The runabout inference-ticket. Analysis, 21, 38–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Sainsbury, M. (1995). Paradoxes (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Salerno, J. (Ed.). (forthcoming). New essays on the knowability paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Steup, M. Knowledge, definitions of. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  18. Vendler, Z. (1972). Res cogitans. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Weinberg, J., Stich, S., & Nichols, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.Google Scholar
  20. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Williams, M. (2001). Problems of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Hus KeyLinkoping UniversityLinkopingSweden

Personalised recommendations