Philosophical Studies

, Volume 133, Issue 2, pp 233–255 | Cite as

Closure, Contrast, and Answer

Open Access


How should the contrastivist formulate closure? That is, given that knowledge is a ternary contrastive state Kspq (s knows that p rather than q), how does this state extend under entailment? In what follows, I will identify adequacy conditions for closure, criticize the extant invariantist and contextualist closure schemas, and provide a contrastive schema based on the idea of extending answers. I will conclude that only the contrastivist can adequately formulate closure.


Philosophical Study Epistemic Logic Closure Schema Knowledge Ascription Relevant Alternative 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.


  1. Belnap, N. and Steel, T. (1976): The Logic of Questions and Answers, and New Haven.Google Scholar
  2. Castañeda, H. (1980): ‘The Theory of Questions, Epistemic Powers, and the Indexical Theory of Knowledge’, in P. French, T. Uehling and H. Wettstein Jr. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy V: Studies in Epistemology, Minneapolis, 193–238.Google Scholar
  3. Cohen S. (1988). ‘How to be a Fallibilist’. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cohen S. (1999). ‘Contextualism, Skepticism and the Structure of Reasons’. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 57–89 .Google Scholar
  5. (1995). Solving the Skeptical Problem’. Philosophical Review 104: 1–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dretske, F. (1970): ‘Epistemic Operators’, Journal of Philosophy 67, 1007--1023.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dretske, F. (1981): ‘The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge’, Philosophical Studies 40, 363--378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Feldman, R. (1995): ‘In Defense of Closure’, Philosophical Quarterly 45, 487--494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Ginzburg, J. (1996): ‘Interrogatives: Questions, Facts and Dialogue’, in S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (London), 385--422.Google Scholar
  10. Groenendijk, J. and M. Stokhof (1997): ‘Questions’, in J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language (Amsterdam), 1055--1124.Google Scholar
  11. (1970). Epistemic Operators’. Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–23 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. (1981). The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge’. Philosophical Studies. 40: 363–78 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. (1995). In Defense of Closure’. Philosophical Quarterly. 45: 487–94 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Ginzburg, J. (1996): ‘Interrogatives: Questions, Facts and Dialogue’, in S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, London, pp. 385–422.Google Scholar
  15. Groenendijk, J. and Stokhof, M. (1997): ‘Questions’, in J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language, Amsterdam, pp. 1055–1124..Google Scholar
  16. Hamblin C. L. (1958). ‘Questions’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 36: 159–68 .Google Scholar
  17. Hawthorne, J. (2004): Knowledge and Lotteries, Oxford.Google Scholar
  18. Heller M. (1999a). Relevant Alternatives and Closure’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 196–208 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. (1999b). The Proper Role for Contextualism in an Anti-Luck Epistemology’. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 115–129 .Google Scholar
  20. Higginbotham, J. (1996): ‘The Semantics of Questions’, in S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, Oxford, pp. 361–383.Google Scholar
  21. Hintikka, J. (1962): Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca.Google Scholar
  22. Johnsen B. (2001). Contextualist Swords, Skeptical Plowshares’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 385–406 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kvanvig, J. (forthcoming): ‘Contextualism, Contrastivism, Relevant Alternatives, and Closure’, Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
  24. Levinson, S. (1983): Pragmatics, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  25. Lewis D. (1982): ‘Whether Report’, in T. Pauli (ed.), Philosophical Essays Dedicated to Lennart A˚qvist on his Fiftieth Birthday, Uppsala, pp. 194–206>.Google Scholar
  26. Lewis D. (1996). ‘Elusive Knowledge’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. (2003). Contrastive Knowledge’. Philosophical Explorations 6: 74–89 .Google Scholar
  28. Nozick, R. (1981): Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  29. Schaffer J. (2004a). From Contextualism to Contrastivism’. Philosophical Studies 119: 73–103 .CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Schaffer J. (2004b). Skepticism Contextualism and Discrimination’. Philosophy Phenomenological Research 69: 138–155 .Google Scholar
  31. Schaffer, J. (2005a): ‘What Shifts? Thresholds, Standards, or Alternatives?’, in G. Preyer and G. Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy, Oxford, pp. 115–130.Google Scholar
  32. Schaffer, J. (2005b): ‘Contrastive Knowledge’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1, pp. 235–271.Google Scholar
  33. Schaffer, J. (forthcoming): ‘Knowing the Answer’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
  34. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2004): Pyrrhonian Skepticism, Oxford.Google Scholar
  35. Stalnaker, R. (1999a): ‘Assertion’, Context and Content, Oxford, pp. 78–95.Google Scholar
  36. Stalnaker, R. (1999b): ‘On the Representation of Context’, Context and Content, Oxford, pp. 96–113.Google Scholar
  37. Stine G. C. (1976). Skepticism Relevant Alternatives and Deductive Closure’. Philosophical Studies 29: 249–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Williamson, T. (2000): Knowledge and its Limits, Oxford.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of Massachusetts-AmherstAmherstUSA

Personalised recommendations