Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 16, Issue 1, pp 33–51 | Cite as

Cognitive extension, enhancement, and the phenomenology of thinking

Article

Abstract

This paper brings together several strands of thought from both the analytic and phenomenological traditions in order to critically examine accounts of cognitive enhancement that rely on the idea of cognitive extension. First, I explain the idea of cognitive extension, the metaphysics of mind on which it depends, and how it has figured in recent discussions of cognitive enhancement. Then, I develop ideas from Husserl that emphasize the agential character of thought and the distinctive way that conscious thoughts are related to one another. I argue that these considerations are necessary for understanding why forms of cognitive extension may diminish our cognitive lives in different ways. This does not lead to a categorical rejection of cognitive enhancement as unethical or bad for human flourishing, but does warrant a conservative approach to the design and implementation of cognitive artifacts.

Keywords

Cognitive enhancement Extended cognition Cognitive phenomenology Husserl 

References

  1. Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  2. Bayne, T., & Montague, M. (Eds.). (2011a). Cognitive phenomenology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bayne, T., & Montague, M. (2011b). Cognitive phenomenology: An introduction. In Bayne & Montague (Eds.), Cognitive phenomenology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bernecker, S. (2014). How to understand the extended mind. Philosophical Issues, 24, 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 18, 227–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Boghossian, P. (2012). What is inference? Philosophical Studies, 169, 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Breyer, T., & Gutland, C. (Eds.). (2015). Phenomenology of thinking: Philosophical investigations into the character of cognitive experiences. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  8. Buller, T. (2013). Neurotechnology, invasiveness and the extended mind. Neuroethics, 6, 593–605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Byerly, R. (2014). The special value of epistemic self-reliance. Ratio, 27, 53–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Clark, A. (2007). Re-inventing ourselves: the plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32, 263–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Clark, A. (2009). Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head. Mind, 118, 963–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Clowes, R. (2015). Thinking in the cloud: the cognitive incorporation of cloud-based technology. Philosophy & Technology, 28, 261–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Crane, T. (2013). “Unconscious Belief and Conscious Thought.” In Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality, 156–73. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Daniels, N. (2000). Normal functioning and the treatment-enhancement distinction. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 9, 309–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Dennett, D. (1981). True believers: The intentional strategy and why it works. In Heath (Ed.), Scientific explanation (pp. 150–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation—Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation and the relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Dror, I., & Harnad, S. (2008). Cognition distributed: How cognitive technology extends Our minds. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Geach, P. (1957). Mental acts. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  23. Georgalis, N. (2006). The Primacy of the Subjective: Foundations for a Unified Theory of Mind and Language. Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Grimm, S. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 515–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Grimm, S. (2012). The value of understanding. Philosophy Compass, 7, 103–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Heersmink, R. (2011). Defending extension theory: A response to Kiran and verbeek. Philosophy and Technology, 25, 121–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Heersmink, R. (2013). A taxonomy of cognitive artifacts: function, information, and categories. The Review of Philosophy & Psychology, 4, 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time. Macquarrie and Robinson (trans.). New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  29. Horgan, T., & Kriegel, U. (2008). Phenomenal intentionality meets the extended mind. The Monist, 91, 347–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–33). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and judgment; investigations in a genealogy of logic. Churchill and Ameriks (trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: studies in phenomenology of the constitution. Rojcewicz and Schuwer (trans). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  33. Husserl, E. (2001a). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: lectures on transcendental logic. Steinbock (trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  34. Husserl, E. (2001b). Logical investigations, Vol. 1. Findlay (trans.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  35. Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Ihde, D. (2011). Husserl’s Galileo needed a telescope! Philosophy and Technology, 24, 69–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Khalifa, K. (2013). The role of explanation in understanding. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 161–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Kiran, A., & Verbeek, P. (2010). Trusting our selves to technology. Knowledge, Technology and Policy, 23, 409–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1995). On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive Science, 18, 513–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Klausen, S. (2008). The phenomenology of propositional attitudes. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 445–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Klein, G., Calderwood, R., & Clinton-Cirocco, A. (2010). Rapid decision making on the fire ground: the original study plus a postscript. Journal of Cognitive Engineering and Decision Making, 4, 186–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kriegel, U. (2003). “Is Intentionality Dependent Upon Consciousness?” Philosophical Studies 116 (3):271–307.Google Scholar
  43. Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013a). Phenomenal intentionality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Kriegel, U. (2013b). The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program. In Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal intentionality (pp. 1–26). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Levy, N. (2007). Rethinking neuroethics in the light of the extended mind thesis. American Journal of Bioethics, 7, 3–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In Reflections and replies: essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 229–58). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  48. Luhmann, N. (1988). Familiarity, confidence, trust: problems and alternatives. In Gambetta (Ed.), Trust: making and breaking cooperative relations (pp. 94–107). Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  49. Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2013). Phenomenology of perception. Landes (trans.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  51. Mohanty, J. N. (1971). Husserl’s concept of intentionality. In Tymieniecka (Ed.), Analecta Husserliana (pp. 100–132). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  52. Nes, A. (2015). The sense of natural meaning in conscious inference. In Breyer and Gutland (Eds.), Phenomenology of thinking. Routledge. 1-22. Accessed from http://philpapers.org/archive/NESTSO-2.pdf.
  53. Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition, or, what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 1–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Pitt, D. (2011). Introspection, phenomenality, and the availability of intentional content. In Bayne and Montague (Eds.), Cognitive phenomenology (pp. 141–173). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Plato. (1892). Phaedrus. Jowett (trans.). The dialogues of plato in five volumes. 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Putnam, H. (1967). The nature of mental states. In Capitan & Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 223–31). Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–93.Google Scholar
  58. Radoilska, L. (2010). An Aristotelian approach to cognitive enhancement. Journal of Value Inquiry, 44, 365–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: from extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  60. Rudder Baker, L. (1995). Explaining attitudes: A practical approach to the mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 253–329.Google Scholar
  64. Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Siewert, C. (2011). Phenomenal thought. In M. Bayne (Ed.), Cognitive phenomenology (pp. 236–267). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Smith, D. W., & Thomasson, A. (2005). Phenomenology and philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Soteriou, M. (2007). Content and the stream of consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 543–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Steinbock, A. (2004). Affection and attention: on the phenomenology of becoming aware. Continental Philosophy Review, 37, 21–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge (pp. 239–54). Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  70. Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44, 510–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Thomasson, A. (2002). Phenomenology and the development of analytic philosophy. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 40, 115–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Walsh, P. (2013). Husserl’s concept of motivation: the logical investigations and beyond. Logical Analysis & History of Philosophy/Philosophiegeschichte Und Logische Analyse, 16, 70–83.Google Scholar
  74. Walsh, P., Yoshimi, J. Forthcoming. Philosophy of mind in the phenomenological tradition. In Kind (Ed.), Philosophy of mind in the 20th and 21st centuries. Routledge.Google Scholar
  75. Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  76. Wrathall, M. (2005). Motives, reasons, and causes. In Carmen & Hansen (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to merleau-ponty (pp. 111–128). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  77. Yoshimi, J. A unifying formalism for Husserlian phenomenology. Unpublished manuscript, University of California, Merced.Google Scholar
  78. Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Zahavi, D. (2015). Self and other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.IrvineUSA

Personalised recommendations