Advertisement

Minds and Machines

, 19:477 | Cite as

Beyond Mind: How Brains Make up Artificial Cognitive Systems

  • Lorenzo Magnani
Article

Abstract

What I call semiotic brains are brains that make up a series of signs and that are engaged in making or manifesting or reacting to a series of signs: through this semiotic activity they are at the same time engaged in “being minds” and so in thinking intelligently. An important effect of this semiotic activity of brains is a continuous process of disembodiment of mind that exhibits a new cognitive perspective on the mechanisms underling the semiotic emergence of meaning processes. Indeed at the roots of sophisticated thinking abilities there is a process of disembodiment of mind that presents a new cognitive perspective on the role of external models, representations, and various semiotic materials. Taking advantage of Turing’s comparison between “unorganized” brains and “logical” and “practical” machines” this paper illustrates the centrality to cognition of the disembodiment of mind from the point of view of the interplay between internal and external representations, both mimetic and creative. The last part of the paper describes the concept of mimetic mind I have introduced to shed new cognitive and philosophical light on the role of computational modeling and on the decline of the so-called Cartesian computationalism.

Keywords

Extended mind Artifactual mediators Abduction Semiotic brains Semiosis  Disembodiment of mind 

References

  1. Brent, J. (2000). A brief introduction to the life and thought of Charles Sanders Peirce. In J. Muller & J. Brent (Eds.), Peirce, semiosis, and psychoanalysis (pp. 1–14). Baltimore and London: John Hopkins.Google Scholar
  2. Colapietro, V. (2000). Futher consequences of a singular capacity. In J. Muller & J. Brent (Eds.), Peirce, semiosis, and psychoanalysis (pp. 136–158). Baltimore and London: John Hopkins.Google Scholar
  3. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Little, Brown, and Company.Google Scholar
  4. Gatti, A., & Magnani, L. (2005) On the representational role of the environment and on the cognitive nature of manipulations. In L. Magnani & R. Dossena (Eds.), Computing, philosophy, and cognition) (pp. 227–242). College Publications, London (Proceedings of the International Conference E-CAP2004.Google Scholar
  5. Hameroff, S. R., Kaszniak, A. W., & Chalmers, D. J. (Eds.). (1999). Toward a science of consciousness III. The third Tucson discussions and debates. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  6. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT. 1992.Google Scholar
  7. Lassègue, J. (1998). Turing. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
  8. Lassègue, J. (2002). Turing entre formel et forme; Remarque sur la convergence des perspectives morphologiques. Intellectica, 35(2), 185–198.Google Scholar
  9. Longo, G. (2002). Laplace, Turing, et la géométrie impossible du “jeu de l’imitation”: Aléas, determinisme e programmes dans le test de Turing. Intellectica, 35(2), 131–161.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  10. Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason, and science. Processes of discovery and explanation. New York: Kluwer /Plenum.Google Scholar
  11. Magnani, L. (2004). Conjectures and manipulations. Computational modeling and the extra-theoretical dimension of scientific discovery. Minds and Machines, 14, 507–537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Magnani, L. (2007). Knowledge as a duty. Distributed morality in a technological world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  13. Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition. The epistemological and eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  14. Magnani, L., & Dossena, R. (2003). Perceiving the infinite and the infinitesimal world: unveiling and optical diagrams and the construction of mathematical concepts. In Proceedings of CogSci2003. CD-ROM produced by X-CD Technologies, Boston, MA.Google Scholar
  15. Magnani, L., Nersessian, N. J., & Pizzi, C. (Eds.). (2002). Logical and computational aspects of model-based reasoning. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  16. Mithen, S. (1996). The Prehistory of the mind, a search for the origins of art, religion, and science. London: Thames and Hudson. 1996.Google Scholar
  17. Mithen, S. (1999). Handaxes and ice age carvings: hard evidence for the evolution of consciousness. In Hameroff, et al., pp. 281–296.Google Scholar
  18. Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958) (CP). Collected papers, 8 Vols. C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (vols. I–VI), (Eds.), & A. W. Burks (vols. VII–VIII) (Ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.Google Scholar
  19. Turing, A. M. (1937). On computable numbers with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42, 230–265.Google Scholar
  20. Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 49, 433–460. Also in (Turing, 1992a), pp. 133–160.CrossRefMathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  21. Turing, A. M. (1969). Intelligent machinery [1948]. In B. Meltzer & D. Michie (Eds.), Machine Intelligence 5:3–23. Also in (Turing, 1992a), pp. 3–23.Google Scholar
  22. Turing, A. M. (1992a). In D. C. Ince (Ed.), Collected works of Alan Turing, Mechanical intelligence. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  23. Turing, A. M. (1992b). In P. T. Saunders (Ed.), Collected works of Alan Turing, Morphogenesis. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and Computational Philosophy LaboratoryUniversity of PaviaPaviaItaly
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophySun Yat-sen UniversityGuangzhou (Canton)People’s Republic of China

Personalised recommendations