Advertisement

Minds and Machines

, Volume 19, Issue 4, pp 453–463 | Cite as

Life and Mind

  • Margaret A. Boden
Article

Abstract

It’s sometimes said, and even more often assumed, that life is necessary for mind. If so, and if A-Life promises to throw light on the nature of life as such, then A-Life is in principle highly relevant to the philosophy of mind and cognitive science. However, very few philosophers have attempted to argue for the relation between life and mind. It’s usually taken for granted. Even those (mostly in the Continental tradition, including some with a following in A-Life) who have insisted on the linkage have stated it rather than justified it. If an evolutionary account of intentionality is acceptable, then perhaps biological life ‘makes room’ for mind. But that claim is problematic, since it’s not clear that the type of self-organization involved in life-as-such must necessarily include evolution. Even if it does, it’s a further step to show that life is strictly necessary for mind.

Keywords

Life Self-organization Evolution Intentionality A-Life 

References

  1. Bedau, M. A. (1996). The nature of life. In M. A. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial life (pp. 332–357). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Boden, M. A. (1972). Purposive explanation in psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
  3. Boden, M. A. (1999). Is metabolism necessary? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 231–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boden, M. A. (2000). Autopoiesis and life. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 1, 1–29.Google Scholar
  5. Boden, M. A. (2006). Mind as machine: A history of cognitive science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Cliff, D., Harvey, I., & Husbands, P. (1993). Explorations in evolutionary robotics. Adaptive Behavior, 2, 73–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cliff, D., & Miller, G. F. (1995). Tracking the red queen: Measurements of adaptive progress in co-evolutionary simulations. In F. Moran, A. Moreno, J. J. Merelo & P. Chacon (Eds.), Advances in Artificial Life: Proceedings of the Third European Conference on Artificial Life (ECAL95) (pp. 200–218). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  8. Edgley, R. (1970). Innate ideas. In G. Vesey (Ed.), Knowledge and necessity (pp. 1–33). London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  9. Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Geach, P. T. (1980). Some remarks on representations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 80–81.Google Scholar
  11. Harvey, I., Husbands, P. & Cliff, D. (1994). Seeing the light: Artificial evolution, real vision. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J.-A. Meyer & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From Animals to Animats 3: Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 392–401). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. Husbands, P., Harvey, I., & Cliff, D. (1995). Circle in the round: State space attractors for evolved sighted robots. Journal of Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 15, 83–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. New York: Harper Collins. (Page-references are to the 2001 edition. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press).Google Scholar
  14. Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Jonas, H. (1990). Heidegger’s resoluteness and resolve: An interview. In G. Neske & E. Kettering (Eds.), Martin Heidegger and national socialism: Questions and answers (pp. 197–203). New York: Paragon House.Google Scholar
  16. Langton, C. G. (1989). Artificial life. In C. G. Langton (Ed.), Artificial life. (pp. 1–47). Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley. (Revised version in M. A. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial life (pp. 39–94, 1996). Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
  17. Lettvin, J. Y., Maturana, H. R., McCulloch, W. S., & Pitts, W. H. (1959). What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain. Proceedings of the Institute of Radio Engineers, 47, 11.Google Scholar
  18. Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Boston: Reidel.Google Scholar
  19. Mays, W. (1952). Can machines think? Philosophy, 27, 148–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Millikan, R. G. (1996). On swampkinds. Mind and Language, 11, 105–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Morris, M. R. (1992). The good and the true. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  24. Papineau, D. (1987). Reality and representation. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Putnam, H. (1962). Dreaming and “depth grammar”. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy (first series) (pp. 211–235). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  26. Ray, T. S. (1992). An approach to the synthesis of life. In C. G. Langton, C. Taylor, J. D. Farmer, & S. Rasmussen (Eds.), Artificial life II (pp. 371–408). Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
  27. Scriven, M. (1953). The mechanical concept of mind. Mind, 62, 230–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.CrossRefMathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  30. Ziff, P. (1959). The feelings of robots. Analysis, 19, 64–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Cognitive Science University of SussexEast SussexUK

Personalised recommendations