Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Through the looking glass: good looks and dignity in care

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are roughly two meanings attached to the concept of dignity: humanitas and dignitas. Humanitas refers to ethical and juridical notions of equality, autonomy and freedom. Much less understood is the meaning of dignitas, which this paper develops as peoples’ engagement with aesthetic values and genres, and hence with differences between people. Departing from a critical reading of Georgio Agamben’s notion of ‘bare life’, I will analyze a case where aesthetics are quite literally at stake: women who lost their hair due to cancer treatment. The analysis shows a complicated interplay between varying evaluations of female baldness by the self and others, mediated by (often strongly negative) cultural imaginaries, and aesthetic genres depicting conventional ways of ‘looking good’. The paper concludes by arguing for a reconnection of the two notions of dignity, and for a rehabilitation of aesthetics in daily life and care as fundamental values for organizing our societies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Qualitative studies of dignity in medicine tend to analyse dignity by listing its components, or the elements of dignity mentioned in a particular care situation (see e.g. Chochinov et al. 2002; Jacobson 2009; Baillie 2007). Philosophers look for theoretical coherence, which they often find by focusing on dignity in relation to human rights (see e.g. McCrudden 2008; Hendriks and Kaulingfreks 2011). Most often Cicero’s reference to dignitas as a difference in social status forms the reason for keeping dignitas at a distance: the fear is to legitimize inequalities and first and second class citizens. See Pols (2013a, b).

  2. For example, Hilhorst (2002), Dekkers (1999) and Düwell (1999) discuss the beauty of the body, and Maio (1999) the importance of good manners for doctors.

  3. This contrasts aesthetics with an ethics of justice or principles. In pre-modern ethics of the good life ethics and aesthetics are much more intertwined. The ethics of the good life life do, however, not reflect on society, but on the behaviour of individuals, see e.g. Nussbaum (2001), Foucault (1990). Feminist philosophy has contested these positions by looking for different ways to conceptualise differences and (gendered) aesthetics in political philosophy (Landess 1988).

  4. I suspect that the loss of a notion of aesthetics in everyday life, has also made the way for philosophers and ethicists to do empirical research more difficult to find.

  5. I use the term social imaginaries to point to singular or rare imgages or events that do not depict a conventions (ordered) aesthetic, but disturb these, either as creative suggestions for new aestheticse, or as examples of a threat to any form of aesthetics (anti-aesthetics).

  6. The forcefeeding of hungerstriking prisoners of Guantanamo Bay, Agamben argues, shows that the last discretion these people had, i.e. to die from starvation, is taken from them, They live in a ‘state of exception’ where they cannot be sacrificed (they are outside the law), but they are not allowed to die, a terrible variety on Agamben’s homo sacer (Agamben 2003).

  7. Interestingly, Agamben himself (2003) develops a completely different line of thought, which I understand as a development of a notion of society as a ‘society without characteristics’, or, as he calls it: a ‘common community’, or a ‘community without identity’ where nobody can be banned because all fit in. Rather than ‘dressing up’ the notion of individuality, as I attempt here, Agamben defines a community without specifications which cannot by its norms exclude any person. For ways to develop this thinking in a care setting: see Ceci et al. (2013).

  8. Using the verb ‘doing disease’ rather than being ill (Mol 2002) is a bit awkward in everyday language use, but it avoides assigning an objective state of ‘being’ to medial takes on discovering and treating disease, whereas the other categories (feeling and looking ill) are denied such ontological realities.

  9. The modern way of ‘doing all the tests’ in one day saves patients a scary time of waiting and not knowing, but the speed in which their fate enrolls is very hard for them to keep up with. Most women talk about this time as an emotional whirlwind without them being able to make sense of it in any way.

  10. More tricky is the relation of optimistic feelings with the state of the tumor, that is critized by people with cancer as leading to a ‘terror of positive thinking’.

  11. Female hair needs to be hidden from the other sex under a scarf in many cultures, strongly linking hair to sexuality, shame and feminine identity. It is not known how men perceive this. Baldness is acceptable for men, but when all body hair is gone, this may be different.

  12. Mann (1998) describes dignity violations as not being seen, being seen as a member of a group, violation of personal space, and humiliation by being separated from a group or social norm. Apart from the third, these match the description of what the bald women experience women perfectly (see also Chochinov 2007). Note that the visual metaphors are to be taken literally in my analysis, and metaphorically in Mann’s—opening up the question how other senses then vision might influence dignitas.

  13. In a Dutch movie featuring a beautiful woman with cancer (Oerlemans 2009) one of the most dramatic scenes is when the hair of the woman is being cut off, effectfully showing that she is being ‘de-humanized’. This has a profound dramatic effect, but is quite different from the way my informants described this situation.

  14. Note that this image of the concentration camp leaves no room for any form of dignitas, whereas survivors of concentration camps did keep up forms of dignitas in order to survive (see the works of Primo Levi). This means that people may posess dignitas even if they are being denied humanitas. Think also of music and dance forms that were developed by groups of people who were kept as slaves.

  15. This may also relate to collective Dutch imaginaries referring to the treatment of female ‘collaborators’, women who engaged in love affairs with German soldiers occupying the Netherlands during WWII. After the war, the heads of these women were shaven publicly, sometimes painted with aggressive paint (Diederichs 2006). This was a form of public execution and humiliation. This imaginary was not referred to by my informants, but may have had an influence. It is a strong enactment of social humiliation and a clear attack on dignity.

  16. Turning something that is deemed to be ugly in one place into something likeable is possible, but does imply a resistance to the aesthetic genres that condemn the proposed look, like ‘punk’ or ‘flower power’.

  17. The method of empirical ethics to morally evaluate these situations would be to compare the aesthetics of the different practices and weighing the consequences of these practices for different individuals (see Pols 2013b).

  18. Interestingly, there are other claimants to this kind of dignity: animals (Singer 1975; Foer 2009), which would also bring up the question why we should not include insects, plants or even bacteria. It would be an interesting thought experiment to imagine what dignitas, and hence sociality, would consist of for a cow or a tulip, and what life forms are feasible and valuable to these subjects newly dressed up with dignity.

  19. Chochinov (2002) seems to oppose palliative care concerned with quality of life to cure as concerned with survival. The intimate relation between humanitas and dignitas, however, links death and survival to care situations –one may die with dignity, or live without it. Cure and (palliative) care are no separate domains.

References

  • Agamben, G. 1998. Homo Sacer. Sovereign power and bare life. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 2003. The coming community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillie, L. 2007. Patient dignity in an acute hospital setting: A case study. International Journal of Nursing Studies 26: 23–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ceci, C., M.E. Purkis, and K. Björnsdóttir. 2013. Theorizing accommodation in supportive home care for older people. Journal of Aging Studies 27: 30–37.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Chochinov, H.M., T. Hack, S. McClement, L. Kristjanson, and M. Harlos. 2002. Dignitiy in the terminally ill: A developing empirical model. Social Science and Medicine 54: 433–443.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Chochinov, H.M. 2002. Dignity conserving care. A new model for palliative care. JAMA 87(17): 2253–2260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chochninov, H.M. 2007. Dignity and the essence of medicine: The A, B, C and D of dignity conserving care. British Medical Journal 335: 184–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Kort, S.J., P.H.B. Willems, J.M. Habraken, J.C.J.M. De Haes, D.L. Willems, and D.J. Richel. 2006. Quality of life versus prolongation of life in patients treated with chemotherapy in advanced colorectal cancer. A review of randomized controlled clinical trials. European Journal of Cancer 42: 835–845.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dekkers, W. 1999. The lived body as aesthetic object in anthropological medicine. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2(2): 117–128.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Diederichs, M. 2006. Wie geschoren wordt moet stil zitten. De omgang van Nederlandse meisjes met Duitse militairen [Who is being shaved, needs to sit still. Dutch girls and German soldiers [the main title refers to a Dutch proverb]. Amsterdam: Boom.

  • Düwell, M. 1999. Aesthetic experience, medical practice, and moral judgement. Critical Remarks on Possibilities to Understand a Complex Relationship, Medicine, Health care & Philosophy 2(2): 161–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgar, 2004. A response to Nordenfelt’s ‘The varieties of dignity’. Health Care Analysis 12(2): 83–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foer, J.S. 2009. Eating animals. Little, Brown and Company.

  • Foucault, M. 1971. L’ordre du discourse. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. 1990. The history of sexuality, vol. 3. London: The Care of Self, Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, A. 2004. Dignity and respect for dignity. Two key health professional values: Implications for nursing practice. Nursing ethics 11(6): 587–599.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hendriks, A., and R.G.A. Kaulingfreks. 2011. Wat is waardigheid? Een briefwisseling tussen een jurist en een filosoof. Den Haag: ZonMw.

  • Hennion, A. 2003. Music and mediation: Toward a new sociology of music. In The cultural study of music: A critical introduction, ed. Martin Clayton, Trevor Herbert, and Richard Middleton. Routledge.

  • Hilhorst, M. 2002. Physical beauty: Only skin deep? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 5: 11–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, N. 2009. A taxonomy of dignity: A grounded theory study. BMC International Health and human rights 9: 3. doi:10.1186/1472-698X/9/3.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, N. 2007. Dingity and health. A review. Social Science and Medicine 64(2): 292–302.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, J. 1988. Women and the public sphere in the age of the French revolution. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leget, C. 2012. Analyzing dignity: A perspective from the ethics of care. Medicine Health Care & Philsopophy. doi:10.1007/s11019-012-9427-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maio, G. 1999. Is etiquette relevant to medical ethics? Ethics and aesthetics n the works of John Gregory (1724–1773). Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2(2): 181–187.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J., and N. Lickiss (eds.). 2007. Perspectives on human dignity. A conversation. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mann, J. 1998. Dignity and health: The UDHR’s revolutionary first article. Health and Human Righst 3(2): 30–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden C. 2008. Human diginity and juridical interpretation of human rights. International law and justice working papers, New york: Institute for international Law and Justice.

  • Meyer, B. (ed.). 2007. Aesthetic formations. Media, religion and the sciences. London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, B., and J. Verrips. 2008. Aesthetics. In Keywords in religion, media and culture, ed. D. Morgan, 20–30. New york: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mol, A. 2002. The body multiple. An ontology of medical practice. Durham: Duke university Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. 2003a. Dignity of the elderly: An introduction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 6: 99–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. 2003b. Dignity and the care of the elderly. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 6: 103–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. 2004. The varieties of dignity. Health Care Analysis 12(2): 69–81.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum .2001. The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in greek tragedy and philosophy, Cambridge UP.

  • Oerlemans, R. (director). 2009. Komt een vrouw bij de dokter (film). Netherlands: Benelux Film distributors.

  • Pols, J. 2013a, forthcoming. Washing the patient. Dignity and aesthetic values in nursing care. Nursing philosophy.

  • Pols. 2013b, forthcoming. Radical relationality. Empirical epistemology in care, care ethics for research. In Moral boundaries redrawn. The significance of Joan Tronto’s argument for professional ethics, political theory and care practice, ed. Olthuis, G., Kohlen, H., and Heier, J. Leuven: Peeters.

  • Pullman, 2002. Human dignity and the ethics and aesthetics of pain and suffering. Theoretical Medicine 23: 75–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. 2011. Changing tastes: How things tasted in the early modern period and how they taste now the hans rausing lecture. Uppsala: Uppsala University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. 1975. Animal liberation: A new ethics for our treatment of animals. New York: New York Review/Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmermans, S. 2005. Death brokering: Constructing culturally appropriate deaths. Sociology of Health & Illness 27(7): 993–1013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Stap, S. 2006. Meisje met de negen pruiken. [Girl with the nine wigs.] Amsterdam: Prometheus.

  • Willems, D. 2010. Varieties of goodness in high-tech homecare. In Care in practice. On tinkering in clinics, homes and farms, ed. A. Mol, I. Moser, and J. Pols, 257–276. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • www.cancerresearchuk.org/cancer-info/cancerstats/types/breast/incidence/uk-breast-cancer-incidence-statistics.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am most grateful to the women who taught me so much about their lives and the importance of ‘looking good’. Many thanks also to Dick Willems for pushing the idea of aesthetics in care and getting in money for this study. I am very grateful to Amade M’charek, Christine Ceci, Thomas Franssen, and Maartje Hoogsteijns for their critical comments on an earlier draft of this paper. This project has been made possible through a grant from ZonMW, palliative care, grant number 1151.0018.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeannette Pols.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pols, J. Through the looking glass: good looks and dignity in care. Med Health Care and Philos 16, 953–966 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9483-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9483-3

Keywords

Navigation