Advertisement

Metascience

, Volume 24, Issue 1, pp 5–24 | Cite as

What-if history of science

Peter J. Bowler: Darwin deleted: Imagining a world without Darwin. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013, ix+318pp, $30.00 HB
  • Alan C. Love
  • Robert J. Richards
  • Peter J. Bowler
Book Symposium

Alan C. Love

Darwinian calisthenics

An athlete engages in calisthenics as part of basic training and as a preliminary to more advanced or intense activity. Whether it is stretching, lunges, crunches, or push-ups, routine calisthenics provide a baseline of strength and flexibility that prevent a variety of injuries that might otherwise be incurred. Peter Bowler has spent 40 years doing Darwinian calisthenics, researching and writing on the development of evolutionary ideas with special attention to Darwin and subsequent filiations among scientists exploring evolution (e.g., Bowler 1976, 1983, 1988, 1989, 1996, 2007). Therefore, we would expect that when Bowler engages in a counterfactual history—imagining a world without Darwin—he is able to avoid historical injury and generate novel insights. My assessment is that the results are mixed. Before we can see why, it is necessary to walk briskly through the main contours of his argument.

Bowler begins with an apologiafor a counterfactual...

References

  1. Amundson, R. 2005. The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of evo-devo. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beatty, J. 2006. Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy 103: 336–362.Google Scholar
  3. Bellon, R. 2011. Inspiration in the harness of daily labor: Darwin, botany, and the triumph of evolution, 1859–1868. Isis 102: 393–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bowler, P.J. 1976. Fossils and progress: Paleontology and the idea of progressive evolution in the nineteenth century. New York: Science History Publications.Google Scholar
  5. Bowler, P.J. 1983. The eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian evolution theories in the decades around 1900. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Bowler, P.J. 1988. The non-Darwinian revolution: Reinterpreting a historical myth. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bowler, P.J. 1989. Evolution: The history of an idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  8. Bowler, P.J. 1996. Life’s splendid drama: Evolutionary biology and the reconstruction of life’s ancestry, 1860–1940. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bowler, P.J. 2007. Monkey trials and gorilla sermons: Evolution and Christianity form Darwin to intelligent design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Brooke, J.H. 1977. Richard Owen, William Whewell, and the Vestiges. British Journal for the History of Science 10: 132–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Darwin, C. 1985. The correspondence of Charles Darwin, eds. Frederick Burkhardt et al., 21 vols., 7. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Darwin, C., and A.R. Wallace. 1858. On the tendency of species to form varieties; and on the perpetuation of varieties and species by natural means of selection. Journal of the Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London. Zoology 3: 45–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Desmond, A., and J.R. Moore. 2009. Darwin’s sacred cause: Race, slavery and the quest for human origins. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
  14. Evans, R. 2014. ‘What If’ is a waste of time. The Guardian, March 13, 2014. http://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/13/counterfactual-history-what-if-waste-of-time.
  15. Gray, A. 1963. Evolutionary teleology. In Darwiniana: Essays, reviews pertaining to Darwinism, ed. A. Hunter Dupree. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Haeckel, E. 1868. Natürliche Schöfungsgeschichte. Berlin: Georg Reimer.Google Scholar
  17. Huxley, T.H. 1900. The reception of the origin of species. In Life and letters of Thomas Henry Huxley, ed. Leonard Huxley, 2 vols., 1. New York: D. Appleton.Google Scholar
  18. Huxley, T.H. 1903. Vestiges of the natural history of creation. 10th ed. In The scientific memoirs of Thomas Henry Huxley. Supplementary volume, eds. Michael Foster, and Ray Lankester, 1–19. London: Macmillan & Co.Google Scholar
  19. Kellert, S.H., H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters. 2006. Introduction: The pluralist stance. In Scientific pluralism, eds. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, vii–xxix. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. XIX. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  20. Love, A.C. 2007. Morphological and paleontological perspectives for a history of evo-devo. In From embryology to evo-devo: A history of developmental evolution, ed. M. Laubichler, and J. Maienschein, 267–307. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Love, A.C. 2009. Marine invertebrates, model organisms, and the modern synthesis: epistemic values, evo-devo, and exclusion. Theory in Biosciences 128: 19–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Martin, J.D. 2013. Is the contingentist/inevitabilist debate a matter of degrees? Philosophy of Science 80: 919–930.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Moore, J.A. 1979. The post-Darwinian controversies: A study of the Protestant struggle to come to terms with Darwin in Great Britain and America, 1870–1900. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Moore, J.A. 1985. Herbert Spencer’s henchmen: The evolution of Protestant liberals in late nineteenth-century America. In Darwinism and divinity: Essays on evolution and religious belief, ed. J.R. Durant, 76–100. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Mivart, St.G.J. 1871. On the genesis of species. New York: D. Appleton and Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Nolan, D. 2013. Why historians (and everyone else) should care about counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies 163: 317–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Radick, G. 2005. Other histories, other biologies. In Philosophy, biology and life, ed. A. O’Hear, 21–47. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Richards, R. 1987.  Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.  Google Scholar
  29. Richards, R. 2008. The tragic sense of life: Ernst Haeckel and the struggle over evolutionary thought. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Secord, J. 2000. Victorian sensation: The extraordinary publication, reception and secret authorship of vestiges of the natural history of creation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  31. Sedgwick, A. 1845. Vestiges of the natural history of creation, London: 1845. Edinburgh Review 82: 1–85.Google Scholar
  32. Spencer, H. 1864. The principles of biology, 2 vols., 1. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
  33. van Wyhe, J. 2007. Mind the gap: Did Darwin avoid publishing his theory? Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 60: 177–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Wallace, A.R. 1911. The world of life: A manifestation of creative power, directive mind and ultimate purpose. London: G. Bell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  • Alan C. Love
    • 1
  • Robert J. Richards
    • 2
  • Peter J. Bowler
    • 3
  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Minnesota Center for Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of Minnesota - Twin CitiesMinneapolisUSA
  2. 2.Fishbein Center for History of Science and MedicineThe University of ChicagoChicagoUSA
  3. 3.School of History and AnthropologyQueen’s UniversityBelfastUK

Personalised recommendations