Skip to main content
Log in

Counterlogicals as Counterconventionals

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We develop and defend a new approach to counterlogicals. Non-vacuous counterlogicals, we argue, fall within a broader class of counterfactuals known as counterconventionals. Existing semantics for counterconventionals (developed by Einheuser (Philosophical Studies, 127(3), 459–482 (2006)) and (Kocurek et al. Philosophers’ Imprint, 20(22), 1–27 (2020)) allow counterfactuals to shift the interpretation of predicates and relations. We extend these theories to counterlogicals by allowing counterfactuals to shift the interpretation of logical vocabulary. This yields an elegant semantics for counterlogicals that avoids problems with the usual impossible worlds semantics. We conclude by showing how this approach can be extended to counterpossibles more generally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Anderson, A.R., & Belnap, N.D. (1975). Entailment: the logic of relevance and necessity Vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Areces, C., & ten Cate, B. (2007). Hybrid logics. In Blackburn, P., Wolter, F., & van Benthem, J. (Eds.) Handbook of modal logic (pp. 821–868): Elsevier.

  3. Ayer, A.J. (1952). Language, truth and logic. New York: Dover Publications, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Barker, C. (2002). The dynamics of vagueness. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bennett, J.F. (2003). A philosophical guide to conditionals. Oxford University Press.

  6. Bernstein, S. (2016). Omission impossible. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2575–2589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Berto, F. (2017). Impossible worlds and the logic of imagination. Erkenntnis, 82(6), 1277–1297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Berto, F., French, R., Priest, G., & Ripley, D. (2018). Williamson on counterpossibles. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 693–713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Briggs, R.A. (2012). Interventionist counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 139–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Brogaard, B., & Salerno, J. (2013). Remarks on counterpossibles. Synthese, 190(4), 639–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013). Conceptual ethics i. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1091–1101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013). Conceptual ethics ii. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1102–1110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Carnap, R. (1937). The logical syntax of language harcourt. New York: Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cohen, D.H. (1987). The problem of counterpossibles. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 29(1), 91–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Cohen, D.H. (1990). In On what cannot be. in: truth or consequences (pp. 123–132). Netherlands, Dordrecht: Springer.

  16. Crossley, J.N., & Humberstone, L. (1977). The logic of actually. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 8, 11–29.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Davies, M., & Humberstone, L. (1980). Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies, 38, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Downing, P.B. (1959). Subjunctive conditionals, time order, and causation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 59(1), 125–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Einheuser, I. (2006). Counterconventional conditionals. Philosophical Studies, 127 (3), 459–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Emery, N., & Hill, C.S. (2016). Impossible worlds and metaphysical explanation: comments on Kment’s modality and explanatory reasoning. Analysis, 77(1), 134–148.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Field, H. (2009). Pluralism in logic. Review of Symbolic Logic, 2 (2), 342–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Field, H. (2009). What is the normative role of logic? Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 83(1), 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Fine, K. (1970). Propositional quantifiers in modal logic. Theoria, 36(3), 336–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Frege, G. (1892). On sense and reference. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100:25–50, translated in 1948. The Philosophical Review, 57(3), 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. French, R., Girard, P., & Ripley, D. (2020). Classical counterpossibles. Review of Symbolic Logic, 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020319000637.

  26. Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Goodman, J. (2004). An extended Lewis/Stalnaker semantics and the new problem of counterpossibles. Philosophical Papers, 33(1), 35–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Gregory, D. (2007). Imagining possibilities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(2), 327–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Hansen, N. (2019). Metalinguistic proposals. Inquiry, 1–19. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1658628.

  30. Harman, G. (1984). Logic and reasoning. Synthese, 60(1), 107–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (what) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Noûs, 34(1), 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Haslanger, S. (2005). What are we talking about? The semantics and politics of social kinds. Hypatia, 20(4), 10–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Jenny, M. (2018). Counterpossibles in science: the case of relative computability. Noûs, 52(3), 530–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. In Almog, J., Perry, J., & Wettstein, H. (Eds.) Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  35. Keefe, R. (2014). What logical pluralism cannot be. Synthese, 191(7), 1375–1390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Kennedy, C., & Willer, M. (2016). Subjective attitudes and counterstance contingency. In Proceedings of SALT, (Vol. 26 pp. 913–933).

  37. Kim, S., & Maslen, C. (2006). Counterfactuals as short stories. Philosophical Studies, 129(1), 81–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford University Press.

  39. Kocurek, A.W. (2020). Logic talk, manuscript.

  40. Kocurek, A.W., Jerzak, E.J., & Rudolph, R.E. (2020). Against conventional wisdom. Philosophers’ Imprint, 20(22), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Kouri Kissel, T. (2018). Logical pluralism from a pragmatic perspective. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(3), 578–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Kouri Kissel, T. (2019). Metalinguistic negotiation and logical pluralism. Synthese, 1–12. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02264-z.

  43. Krakauer, B. (2012). Counterpossibles. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  44. Kripke, S.A. (1971). Identity and necessity. In Munitz, M.K. (Ed.) Identity and individuation (pp. 135–164). New York: New York University Press.

  45. Kripke, S.A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 620–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Kung, P. (2016). You really do imagine it: against error theories of imagination. Noûs, 50(1), 90–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Lewis, D.K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Blackwell Publishing.

  49. Locke, T. (2019). Counterpossibles for modal normativists. Synthese, 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02103-1.

  50. Lycan, W.G. (2001). Real conditionals. Clarendon Press.

  51. MacFarlane, J. (2004). In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought?, unpublished.

  52. MacFarlane, J. (2016). Vagueness as indecision. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 90(1), 255–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Mares, E.D. (1997). Who’s afraid of impossible worlds? Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(4), 516–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Mares, E.D. (2012). Relevance logic. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-relevance/.

  55. McConnell-Ginet, S. (2006). Why defining is seldom just semantics: marriage and marriage. In Birner, B., & Ward, G. (Eds.) Drawing the boundaries of meaning: neo-gricean studies in pragmatics and semantics in honor of Laurence R. Horn (pp. 223–246). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

  56. McConnell-Ginet, S. (2008). Words in the world: how and why meanings can matter. Language, 83, 497–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Muskens, R.A. (1991). Hyperfine-grained meanings in classical logic. Logique et Analyse, 34(133/134), 159–176.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: a modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(4), 535–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Plunkett, D. (2015). Which concepts should we use?: metalinguistic negotiations and the methodology of philosophy. Inquiry, 58(7-8), 828–874.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Plunkett, D., & Sundell, T. (2013). Disagreement and the semantics of normative and evaluative terms. Philosopher’s Imprint, 13, 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Popper, K. (1959). On subjunctive conditionals with impossible antecedents. Mind, 68(272), 518–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Popper, K. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge.

  63. Priest, G. (2008). Logical pluralism hollandaise. Australasian Journal of Logic, 6, 210–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Putnam, H. (1969). Is logic empirical?. In Boston studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 216–241). Dordrecht: Springer.

  65. Quine, W.V.O. (1970). Deviant logics. In Philosophy of logic (pp. 80–94).

  66. Read, S. (2006). Monism: the one true logic. In de Vidi, D., & Kenyon, T. (Eds.) A logical approach to philosophy: essays in memory of Graham Solomon: Springer.

  67. Ripley, D. (2016). Experimental philosophical logic. In Sytsma, J. (Ed.) A companion to experimental philosophy, Wesley Buckwalter, chap 36 (pp. 523–534).

  68. Russell, G. (2008). One true logic? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 37(6), 593–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Sandgren, A., & Tanaka, K. (2019). Two kinds of logical impossibility. Noûs, 1–12. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12281.

  70. Stalnaker, R.C. (1978). Assertion. In Syntax and semantics (pp. 315–332): Oxford University Press.

  71. Steinberger, F. (2019). Logical pluralism and logical normativity. Philosophers’ Imprint, 19(12), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Steinberger, F. (2019). Three ways in which logic might be normative. Journal of Philosophy, 116(1), 5–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  73. Vander Laan, D.A. (2004). Counterpossibles and similarity. In Jackson, F., & Priest, G. (Eds.) Lewisian themes.

  74. van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92(1/2), 67–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  75. Vetter, B. (2016). Counterpossibles (not only) for dispositionalists. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 2681–2700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  76. Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Blackwell Publishers.

  77. Williamson, T. (2009). Probability and danger. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy, 4, 1–35. http://www.amherstlecture.org/williamson2009/.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Williamson, T. (2017). Counterpossibles in semantics and metaphysics. Argumenta, 2(2), 195–226.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53(1), 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to Bob Beddor, Kelly Gaus, Jens Kipper, Daniel Nolan, Dave Ripley, Rachel Rudolph, Alex Sandgren, Zeynep Soysal, James Walsh, and two anonymous referees for their helpful comments. This paper was presented at the Richard Wollheim Society (2018), the Melbourne Logic Seminar (2018), the Central APA (2019), the Cornell Workshop in Linguistics & Philosophy (2019), the Australian National University (2020), the faculty reading group at the National University of Singapore (2019), and Zeynep Soysal’s hyperintensionality seminar at the University of Rochester (2020). We are grateful to the audience members of all these venues for their feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander W. Kocurek.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

In this A, we establish that the impossible worlds semantics and the expressivist semantics generate the same logic over Ł, i.e., that \(\vDash _{\textsf {i}} = \vDash _{\exp }\). To do this, we establish the following:

Theorem 1

  1. 1.

    For any expressivist model \(\mathcal {E} = \langle W,f \rangle \) and any xIW, there is a impossible worlds model \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}} = \langle W^{\textsf {i}},P^{\textsf {i}},f^{\textsf {i}},V^{\textsf {i}} \rangle \) and a wWi such that for all ϕ ∈Ł:

    $$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathcal{E},x \Vdash_{\exp} \phi & \quad{\Leftrightarrow}\quad \mathcal{E}^{\textsf{i}},w \Vdash_{\textsf{i}} \phi. \end{array} $$

    When xCIW, we can take wPi.

  2. 2.

    For any impossible worlds model \(\mathcal {I} = \langle W,P,f,V \rangle \) and any wW, there is a expressivist model \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp } = \langle W^{\exp },f^{\exp } \rangle \) and an \(x \in I_{W^{\exp }}\) such that for all ϕ ∈Ł:

    $$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathcal{I},w \Vdash_{\textsf{i}} \phi & \quad{\Leftrightarrow}\quad \mathcal{I}^{\exp},x \Vdash_{\exp} \phi. \end{array} $$

    When wP, we can take \(x \in CI_{W^{\exp }}\).

Corollary 1

For any \({\Gamma } \mathrel {\subseteq } \L \) and ϕ ∈Ł, \({\Gamma } \vDash _{\textsf {i}} \phi \) iff \({\Gamma } \vDash _{\exp } \phi \).

It is easiest to establish Theorem 1(a) first.

Proof Proof (Theorem 1(a))

Suppose first that xCIW. Define \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}} = \langle W^{\textsf {i}},P^{\textsf {i}},f^{\textsf {i}},V^{\textsf {i}} \rangle \) as follows:

  • Wi = IW

  • Pi = W ×{cx}

  • for each yWi and \(X \mathrel {\subseteq } W^{\textsf {i}}\), fi(X,y) = f(X,y)

  • for each yPi, Vi(p,y) = 1 iff wycy(p)

  • for each yPi, Vi(ϕ,y) = 1 iff \(\mathcal {E},y \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \).

Clearly, \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}}\) is a impossible worlds model and xPi. It suffices to show that for any ϕ and any yIW:

$$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathcal{E},y \Vdash_{\exp} \phi & \quad {\Leftrightarrow}\quad \mathcal{E}^{\textsf{i}},y \Vdash_{\textsf{i}} \phi. \end{array} $$

If yPi, then by construction, \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}},y \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \phi \) iff Vi(ϕ,y) = 1 iff \(\mathcal {E},y \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \). If yPi, then we proceed by induction. The atomic case holds by definition of Vi. The other cases are straightforward since cy = cx is classical and since Pi = W ×{cx}.

Now suppose xCIW. Then we can define \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}}\) as above except now we take Pi = CIW. Then \(\mathcal {E},x \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \) iff \(\mathcal {E}^{\textsf {i}},x \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \phi \) by construction of Vi. □

Theorem 1(a) is not terribly surprising in retrospect. All it says is that anything that is i-valid is also \(\exp \)-valid. But i-validity is pretty weak without further constraints. One way to make that clear is to observe that, as far as the logic is concerned, counterfactuals behave exactly like distinct atomic sentences.

Definition 1

An Ł-formula is an S5-formula if it does not contain . An Ł-formula is a counterfactual if its main connective is .

Proposition 1

Let \({\mathscr{M}} = \langle P,i \rangle \) be an S5-model (where \(i(p) \mathrel {\subseteq } P\) for all p ∈At) and let \({\Phi }:{P}\rightarrow \wp ({\mathscr{L}})\) map every wP to a set Φw of counterfactuals. Then there is an impossible worlds model \(\mathcal {I} = \langle {W,P,f,V}\rangle \) such that for any wP:

  1. 1.

    if ϕ is an S5-formula, then \(\mathcal {I},w \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \phi \) iff \({\mathscr{M}},w \Vdash _{\textbf {S5}} \phi \)

  2. 2.

    if ψ is a counterfactual, then \(\mathcal {I},w \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \psi \) iff ψ ∈Φw.

Proof

WLOG, we may assume that P is disjoint from Ł and from (Ł × P). Define \(\mathcal {I} = \langle P \cup \L \cup (\L \times P),P,f,V \rangle \), where:

  • for each p ∈At and wP, V (p,w) = 1 iff wi(p)

  • for each ϕ ∈Ł and α ∈Ł, V (ϕ,α) = 1 iff α = ϕ

  • for each ϕ ∈Ł and 〈α,w〉∈ (Ł × P), V (ϕ,〈α,w〉) = 1 iff

  • f is any selection function with the following property: if X ∩Ł = {α} and wP, then f(X,w) = {〈α,w〉}.

It is easy to establish (i) by induction. As for (ii), note that \(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {I}} \cap \L = \{\alpha \}\), so \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {I}},w) = \{\langle {\alpha ,w}\rangle \}\). Hence, iff \(\mathcal {I},\langle {\alpha ,w}\rangle \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \beta \), i.e., V (β,〈α,w〉) = 1, which holds iff . □

Corollary 2

Let 𝜃 be any consistent S5-formula, and let 𝜃 be the result of simultaneously uniformly substituting one or more atomic sentences in 𝜃 for distinct counterfactuals. Then 𝜃 is i-satisfiable.

Proof

Let \({q}_1, \dots , {q}_n\) be the atomics in 𝜃 that are substituted for distinct counterfactuals \({\psi }_1, \dots , {\psi }_n\) resulting in 𝜃. Since 𝜃 is consistent, it is S5-satisfiable. Let \({\mathscr{M}},w \Vdash _{\textbf {S5}} \theta \). For each \(v \in W^{{\mathscr{M}}}\), define:

$$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {\Phi}_v \mathrel{:=} \{\psi_{i} | \mathcal{M},v \Vdash_\textbf{S5} q_i\} \end{array} $$

By Proposition 1, this guarantees us an S5-equivalent impossible worlds model \(\mathcal {I}\) such that \(\mathcal {I},v \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \psi \) iff ψ ∈Φv where ψ is a counterfactual. Moreover, in this model, . And since \(\mathcal {I},w \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \theta \), it follows that \(\mathcal {I},w \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \theta ^{*}\). □

Corollary 2 effectively says that there are no non-trivial valid inferences governing counterfactuals in the impossible worlds semantics: any inference with counterfactuals that’s i-valid is already S5-valid.

Theorem 1(b) is harder to establish. The main issue is that while hyperconventions are allowed to redefine the semantic value of the boolean connectives, they cannot touch the semantics of . But in the impossible worlds semantics, any set of Ł-formulas is satisfied at some (perhaps impossible) world in some model, including those containing counterfactuals. Thus, if we are to establish Theorem 1(b), we need to establish the expressivist analogue of Proposition 1. Indeed, this can be done, though the proof is more involved.

Proposition 2

Let \({\mathscr{M}} = \langle W,i \rangle \) be an S5-model and let \({\Phi }:{P}\rightarrow \wp ({\mathscr{L}})\) map every wW to a set Φw of counterfactuals. Then there is a expressivist model \(\mathcal {E} = \langle W,f \rangle \) and a classical hyperconvention c such that for any wW:

  1. (i)

    if ϕ is an S5-formula, then \(\mathcal {E},w,c \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \) iff \({\mathscr{M}},w \Vdash _{\textbf {S5}} \phi \)

  2. (ii)

    if ψ is a counterfactual, then \(\mathcal {E},w,c \Vdash _{\exp } \psi \) iff ψ ∈Φw.

Proof

Since S5 is invariant under bisimulation contraction (and so, invariant under duplication of worlds), we may assume WLOG that W is infinite. We define c simply as the classical hyperconvention over W where c(p) = i(p) for all p ∈At.

We now set out to define f. Fix an arbitrary w0W. Let \({h}:{{\mathscr{L}}}\rightarrow {W - \{w_{0},w\}}\) be a bijection. We’ll write wϕ in place of h(ϕ) throughout. Now, let \({\Gamma } \subseteq \L \). Define the hyperconvention cΓ as follows (where and \(\circ \in \{\wedge ,\vee ,\rightarrow \}\)):

$$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} c_{\Gamma}(p) & =& { \begin{cases} \{w_p,w_0\} & \text{if } p \in {\Gamma} \\ \{w_p\} & \text{otherwise} \end{cases}} \\ c_{\Gamma}(\star)(X) & =& { \begin{cases} \{w_{\star\phi} ~|~ w_\phi \in X\} \cup \{w_0\} & \parbox[t]{.5\textwidth}{if $\star\phi \in {\Gamma}$ whenever $w_{\phi} \in X$} \\ \{w_{\star\phi} ~|~w_\phi \in X\} & \text{otherwise} \end{cases}} \\ c_{\Gamma}(\mathrel{\circ})(X,Y) & {=}& { {{\begin{cases} \{w_{\phi \mathrel{\circ} \psi} ~|~ w_\phi \in X \text{ and } w_\psi \in Y\} \cup \{w_0\} & \parbox[t]{.35\textwidth}{if $\phi \mathrel{\circ} \psi \in {\Gamma}$ whenever $w_{\phi} \in X$ and $w_{\psi} \in Y$} \\ \{w_{\phi \mathrel{\circ} \psi} ~|~w_\phi \in X \text{ and } w_\psi \in Y\} & \text{otherwise} \end{cases}}}} \end{array} $$

Let . Define f as follows:

Let \(\mathcal {E} = \langle W,f \rangle \). It is easy to check that (i) holds by induction. So we just need to establish (ii). First, some intermediate claims:

Claim 1

For any Γ and any ϕ,ψ: \(\mathcal {E},w_{\phi },c_{\Gamma } \Vdash \psi \) iff ϕ = ψ.

Proof

By induction. The atomic case holds by definition of cΓ. The cases for the connectives is straightforward. For the counterfactual, iff \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w_{\phi },c_{{\Gamma }}) \subseteq \llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\). By induction hypothesis, \(\langle {w_{\gamma },c_{{\Gamma }}}\rangle \in \llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\) iff γ = β. Hence, \(\llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}} \neq I_{W}\), which means \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w_{\phi },c_{{\Gamma }}) \subseteq \llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\) iff \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w_{\phi },c_{{\Gamma }}) = \{\langle {w_{\beta },c_{{\Gamma }}}\rangle \}\), which holds iff . But again by induction hypothesis, \(\langle {w_{\alpha },c_{{\Gamma }}}\rangle \in \llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\). Thus, iff . □

Claim 2

For any Γ and any ϕ: \(\mathcal {E},w_{0},c_{\Gamma } \Vdash \phi \) iff ϕ ∈Γ.

Proof

By induction. The atomic case holds by definition of cΓ. The cases for the connectives is straightforward using Claim 1 and the inductive hypothesis. For the counterfactual, iff \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }}) \subseteq \llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\). By Claim 1, \(\langle {w_{\gamma },c_{{\Gamma }}}\rangle \in \llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\) iff γ = α. So \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }}) = \{\langle {w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }^{\alpha }}}\rangle \}\). Hence, \(\mathcal {E},w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }} \Vdash \) iff \(\mathcal {E},w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }^{\alpha }} \Vdash \beta \). But again by induction hypothesis, this holds iff β ∈Γα, i.e., . □

We are now ready to prove (ii). iff \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w,c) \subseteq \llbracket {\beta }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\). By Claim 1, \(\langle w_{\gamma },c_{{\Phi }_{w}} \rangle \in \llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}}\) iff γ = α. Hence, \(f(\llbracket {\alpha }\rrbracket ^{\mathcal {E}},w,c) = \{\langle {w_{0},c_{{\Phi }_{w}^{\alpha }}}\rangle \}\). So iff \(\mathcal {E},w_{0},c_{{\Phi }_{w}^{\alpha }} \Vdash \beta \), which by Claim 2 holds iff \(\beta \in {\Phi }_{w}^{\alpha }\), i.e., . □

Corollary 3

Let 𝜃 be any consistent S5-formula, and let 𝜃 be the result of uniformly substituting one or more atomic sentences in 𝜃 for distinct counterfactuals. Then 𝜃 is \(\exp \)-satisfiable.

Now we can establish Theorem 1(b):

Proof Proof (Theorem 1(b))

Let \(\mathcal {I} = \langle W,P,f,V \rangle \) and first let wP. Let:

$$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {\Phi} & {=}& \{\phi ~|~ \phi \text{ is an $\textbf{S5}$-formula and } \mathcal{I},w \Vdash_\textsf{i} \phi] \\ {\Psi} & {=}& \{\phi~|~\phi \text{ is a counterfactual and } \mathcal{I},w \Vdash_\textsf{i} \phi]. \end{array} $$

By Proposition 2, there is a expressivist model \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp } = \langle W,f^{\exp } \rangle \) and a classical hyperconvention c such that \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp },w,c \Vdash _{\exp } {\Phi } \cup {\Psi }\) and if ϕ is a counterfactual not in Ψ, \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp },w,c \nVdash _{\exp } \phi \). Hence, by a simple induction, \(\mathcal {I},w \Vdash _{\textsf {i}} \phi \) iff \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp },w,c \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \).

Now let wP. Let Γ = {ϕ | V (ϕ,w) = 1} and let \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp }\) be 〈W,f〉 where f is constructed as in Proposition 2. Then by Claim 2, \(\mathcal {I}^{\exp },w_{0},c_{{\Gamma }} \Vdash _{\exp } \phi \) iff ϕ ∈Γ. Hence, we can take x = 〈w0,cΓ〉. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kocurek, A.W., Jerzak, E.J. Counterlogicals as Counterconventionals. J Philos Logic 50, 673–704 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09581-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09581-6

Keywords

Navigation