Advertisement

Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 36, Issue 1, pp 1–32 | Cite as

Modal Logic for Other-World Agnostics: Neutrality and Halldén Incompleteness

  • Lloyd Humberstone
Article

Abstract

The logic of ‘elsewhere,’ i.e., of a sentence operator interpretable as attaching to a formula to yield a formula true at a point in a Kripke model just in case the first formula is true at all other points in the model, has been applied in settings in which the points in question represent spatial positions (explaining the use of the word ‘elsewhere’), as well as in the case in which they represent moments of time. This logic is applied here to the alethic modal case, in which the points are thought of as possible worlds, with the suggestion that its deployment clarifies aspects of a position explored by John Divers un-der the name ‘modal agnosticism.’ In particular, it makes available a logic whose Halldén incompleteness explicitly registers the agnostic element of the position – its neutrality as between modal realism and modal anti-realism.

Key words

Halldén completeness modal logic possible worlds 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    van Benthem, J. (1985): Modal Logic and Classical Logic, Bibliopolis, Naples.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Boolos, G. (1979): The Unprovability of Consistency, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Boolos, G. (1993): The Logic of Provability, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Divers, J. (2002): Possible Worlds, Routledge, London.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Divers, J. (2003): Possible-worlds semantics without possible worlds, paper presented at the Melbourne University Logic Seminar, November 14.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Divers, J. (2006): Possible-worlds semantics without possible worlds: The agnostic approach, Mind 115, 187–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Divers, J. (2005): Agnosticism about other worlds: A new antirealist programme in modality, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69, 659–684.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Fine, K. (1970): Propositional quantifiers in modal logic, Theoria 36, 336–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Fine, K. (1977): ‘Postscript’ to A. N. Prior and K. Fine, Worlds, Times and Selves, Duckworth, London.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Gabbay, D. (1981): An irreflexivity lemma with applications to axiomatizations of conditions on linear frames, in U. Mönnich (ed.), Aspects of Philosophical Logic, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 67–89.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Goranko, V. (1995): A note on derivation rules in modal logic, Bull. Sect. Log. 24, 98–104.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Goranko, V. and Passy, S. (1992): Using the universal modality: Gains and questions, J. Log. Comput. 2, 5–30.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Hughes, G. E. and Cresswell, M. J. (1968): An Introduction to Modal Logic, Methuen, London.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Hughes, G. E. and Cresswell, M. J. (1996): A New Introduction to Modal Logic, Routledge, London.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Humberstone, L. (1983): Inaccessible worlds, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 24, 346–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Humberstone, L. (1987): The modal logic of “all and only”, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 28, 177–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Humberstone, L. (2000): Parts and partitions, Theoria 66, 41–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Humberstone, L. (2004): Two-dimensional adventures, Philos. Stud. 118, 17–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Humberstone, L. (2004): Yet another “choice of primitives” warning: normal modal logics, Log. Anal. 47, 395–407.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Humberstone, L. (2005): Béziau's translation paradox, Theoria 71, 138–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Humberstone, L. (2005): ‘Modality,’ Chapter 20, in F. Jackson and M. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, Oxford University Press, pp. 534–614.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Jansana, R. (1994): Some logics related to von Wright's logic of place, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 35, 88–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Kracht, M. (1999): Tools and Techniques in Modal Logic, North-Holland (Elsevier), Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Kremer, P. (1997): Defining relevant implication in a propositionally quantified S4, J. Symb. Log. 62, 1057–1069.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Kripke, S. A. (1965) Semantical analysis of modal logic II. Non-normal modal propositional calculi, in J. W. Addison, L. Henkin and A. Tarski (eds.), The Theory of Models, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 206–220.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Lambert, K., Leblanc, H. and Meyer, R. K. (1969): A liberated version of S5, Arch. Math. Log. Grundl.forsch. 12, 151–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Lemmon, E. J. (1966): A note on Halldén-incompleteness, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 7, 296–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Lemmon, E. J., Meredith, C. A., Meredith, D., Prior, A. N. and Thomas, I. (1969): Calculi of pure strict implication, in J. W. Davis, D. J. Hockney and W. K. Wilson (eds.), Philosophical Logic, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 215–250.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Lemmon, E. J. and Scott, D. S. (1966): An introduction to modal logic, in K. Segerberg (ed.), American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series, Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1977.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Lemon, O. and Pratt, I. (1997): On the incompleteness of modal logics of space: Advancing complete modal logics of place, in M. Kracht, M. de Rijke, H. Wansing and M. Zakharyeschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic '96, CSLI Publications, Stanford, pp. 1–18.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Lewis, C. I. and Langford, C. H. (1959): Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications. (First edn. 1932.)Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Lewis, D. (1983): Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Lewis, D. (1986): On the Plurality of Worlds, Blackwell, Oxford.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Mackie, J. L. (1977): Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Makinson, D. (1973): A warning about the choice of primitive operators in modal logic, J. Philos. Log. 2, 193–196.Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    Meredith, C. A. and Prior, A. N. (1965): Modal logic with functorial variables and a contingent constant, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 6, 99–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Meredith, C. A. and Prior, A. N. (1964): Investigations into implicational S5, Z. math. Log. Grundl. Math. 10, 203–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    McKinsey, J. C. C. (1953): Systems of modal logic not unreasonable in the sense of Halldén, J. Symb. Log. 18, 109–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. 39.
    Morgan, C. G. (1974): Liberated brouwerian modal logic, Dialogue 13, 505–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Morgan, C. G. (1975): Liberated versions of T, S4 and S5, Arch. Math. Log. Grundl. forsch. 17, 85–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. 41.
    Morgan, C. G. (1975): Weak liberated versions of T and S4, J. Symb. Log. 40, 25–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Morgan, C. G. (1979): Note on a strong liberated modal logic and its relevance to possible world scepticism, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 20, 718–722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. 43.
    Pizzi, C. (1999): Contingency logics and propositonal quantification, Manuscrito, CLE (UNICAMP, São Paulo) 22, 283–303.Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Prior, A. N. (1967): Past, Present and Future, Clarendon, Oxford.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Prior, A. N. (1971): Objects of Thought, Clarendon, Oxford.Google Scholar
  46. 46.
    de Rijke, M. (1992): The modal logic of inequality, J. Symb. Log. 57, 566–584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. 47.
    Schumm, G. F. (1993): Why does Halldén-completeness matter? Theoria 59, 192–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. 48.
    Segerberg, K. (1976): “Somewhere else” and “Some other time”, in Wright and Wrong: Mini-Essays in Honor of George Henrik von Wright on his Sixtieth Birthday, Publications of the Group in Logic and Methodology of Real Finland, Vol. 3, Åbo Akademi, pp. 61–64.Google Scholar
  49. 49.
    Segerberg, K. (1980): A note on the logic of elsewhere, Theoria 46, 183–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. 50.
    Venema, Y. (1993): Derivation rules as anti-axioms in modal logic, J. Symb. Log. 58, 1003–1034.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. 51.
    von Wright, G. H. (1979): A modal logic of place, in E. Sosa (ed.), The Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher: Discussions and Replies, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 65–73.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Monash UniversityVictoriaAustralia

Personalised recommendations