Advertisement

Journal of Medical Humanities

, Volume 34, Issue 2, pp 177–196 | Cite as

Queerin’ the PGD Clinic

Human Enhancement and the Future of Bodily Diversity
  • Robert Sparrow
Article

Abstract

Disability activists influenced by queer theory and advocates of “human enhancement” have each disputed the idea that what is “normal” is normatively significant, which currently plays a key role in the regulation of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). Previously, I have argued that the only way to avoid the implication that parents have strong reasons to select children of one sex (most plausibly, female) over the other is to affirm the moral significance of sexually dimorphic human biological norms. After outlining the logic that generates this conclusion, I investigate the extent to which it might also facilitate an alternative, progressive, opening up of the notion of the normal and of the criteria against which we should evaluate the relative merits of different forms of embodiment. This paper therefore investigates the implications of ideas derived from queer theory for the future of PGD and of PGD for the future of queerness.

Keywords

Queer theory Disability studies Bioethics Preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) Human enhancement Sex 

Notes

Acknowledgments

The research for this paper was supported under the Australian Research Council’s Future Fellowships funding scheme (project FT100100481). The views expressed herein are those of the author and are not necessarily those of the Australian Research Council.

Endnotes

1 Medical science has, of course, long had ambitions to shape future as well as contemporary bodies, most notoriously with its enthusiasm for eugenics programs that arose alongside the development of the science of genetics (Kevles 1985). However, only since the development of technologies of prenatal testing has it had the power to do so.

2 Whether “normal functioning” here should be understood as normal functioning for the individual being treated or “normal human functioning” is a further, controversial, question, with important implications for the logic of the debate about enhancement.

3 The exception to the general rule that individuals are not harmed by non-person-affecting decisions involves situations where a person is born into an existence so wretched that it is rational for them to prefer to be dead. In this case we may wish to say that they have been harmed by being brought into existence (Steinbock and McClamrock 1994; Strong 2005).

4 Both the original (Savulescu 2001) and the revised (Savulescu and Kahane 2009) statement of the principle of “procreative beneficence” also imply that parents are obligated to undertake PGD in order to allow such selection. For criticism of this claim see, de Melo-Martin 2004.

5 An important recent exception here is Elster (2011) who claims that the arguments Savulescu uses to support maximising our children’s welfare also argue in favour of an obligation to maximise social welfare.

6 For a useful introduction, see Griffin (1986) and Sumner (1996).

7 These claims are jarring because, of course, in sexist societies none of them are likely to be true. However, for reasons that will be provided below, parents’ reasoning about which embryo will have the best life prospects should arguably discount the impact of social injustice such as sexism.

8 At the risk of endorsing an ad hominem argument, I can’t help but feel that the hostility with which this argument has been received by advocates of human enhancement reflects, at least in part, the discomfort of this overwhelmingly male group of writers experiences at realising that they are by their own lights “suboptimal”.

9 This is not to deny that people are notoriously bad at evaluating the well-being of other individuals, for instance when they try to predict the impact of a disability on someone's well-being. My point is only that it is wildly implausible to insist that we can have no idea about what would improve or reduce the well-being of future individuals considered in the abstract.

10 At high latitudes, higher levels of melatonin (dark skin) increase the risk of vitamin D deficiency and its associated health impacts (Ponsonby, McMichael, and Van der Mei 2002; Yuen and Jablonski 2010).

11 Yet whether social justice would require that men could become pregnant (Sparrow 2008b) or would be capable of extending male life expectancy to that of women is unclear to say the least.

12 It arguably also requires an account of the normal trajectory of the ageing process, given that what might be therapy for someone in their 20s may be enhancement for someone in their 70s.

13 Importantly, PGD can only affect the rate at which individuals with particular conditions are born into a community. Diverse forms of embodiment as a result of trauma, disease, or elective surgery, will always continue to exist.

References

  1. Agar, N. 2004. Liberal eugenics: in defence of human enhancement. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  2. Anderson, W.F. 1989. “Human gene therapy: why draw a line?” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14 (6): 681–693.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Asch, A. 2000. “Why I haven’t changed my mind about prenatal diagnosis: reflections and refinements.” In Prenatal testing and disability rights, edited by E. Parens and A. Asch, 234–258. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bailey, R. 2005. Liberation biology: the scientific and moral case for the biotech revolution. Amherst, New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
  5. Baily, M.A. 2000. “Why I had amniocentesis.” In Prenatal testing and disability rights, edited by E. Parens and A. Asch, 64–71. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Bostrom, N., and T. Ord. 2006. “The reversal test: eliminating status quo bias in applied ethics.” Ethics 116 (4): 656–679.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brock, D. 1995. “The non identity problem and genetic harms—the case of wrongful handicaps.” Bioethics 9 (3/4): 269–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Buchanan, A. 1996. “Choosing who will be disabled: genetic intervention and the morality of inclusion.” Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (1): 18–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. ———. 2011. Beyond humanity? The ethics of biomedical enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  10. Buchanan, A., D.W. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler. 2000. From Chance to Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Butler, J. 1993. Bodies that matter: on the discursive limits ofsex.” New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  12. ———. 2004. Undoing gender. Boca Raton: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.Google Scholar
  13. Cahill, L. 2005. “His brain, her brain.” Scientific American 292 (5): 40-47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Charlton, J.I. 1998. Nothing about us without us: disability oppression and empowerment. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  15. Davis, A. 1987. “Women with disabilities: abortion and liberation.” Disability, Handicap & Society 2 (3): 275-84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Davis, D.S. 2001. Genetic dilemmas: reproductive technology, parental choices, and childrens futures. New York, NY & London: Routledge. Google Scholar
  17. Davis, L.J. 1995. Enforcing normalcy: disability, deafness, and the body. London; New York: Verso.Google Scholar
  18. de Melo-Martin, I. 2004. “On our obligation to select the best children: a reply to Savulescu.” Bioethics 18 (1): 72-83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Dreger, A.D. 1998. Hermaphrodites and the medical invention of sex. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  20. ———. ed. 1999. Intersex in the age of ethics. Hagerstown, Md.: University Publishing Group.Google Scholar
  21. Elliott, C. 2003. Better than well: American medicine meets the American dream. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
  22. Elster, J. 2011. “Procreative beneficence – cui bono?” Bioethics 25 (9): 482–488, NovemberCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Fausto-Sterling, A. 2000. Sexing the body: gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  24. Feinberg, J. 1980. “The child’s right to an open future.” In Whose child? childrens rights, parental authority, and state power, edited by W. Aiken and H. LaFollette, 124-153. Totowa, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams & Co.Google Scholar
  25. Fine, C. 2010. Delusions of gender: the real science behind sex differences. London: Icon.Google Scholar
  26. Foucault, M. 1994. The birth of the clinic: an archaeology of medical perception. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
  27. Gleicher, N., and V. Karande. 2002. “Gender selection for non-medical indications.” Fertility and Sterility 78 (3): 460–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Glover, J. 2006. Choosing children: genes, disability, and design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Green, R.M. 2007. Babies by design: the ethics of genetic choice. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Griffin, J. 1986. Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  31. Grosz, E.A. 1994. Volatile Bodies: toward a corporeal feminism. St. Leonards, N.S.W.: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  32. Habermas, J. 2003. The future of human nature. Cambridge, England: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  33. Harris, J. 1993. ”Is gene therapy a form of eugenics?” Bioethics 7 (2/3): 178–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. ———. 1998. Clones, genes and immortality: ethics and the genetic revolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. ———. 2001. “One principle and three fallacies of disability studies.” Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (6): 383–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. ———. 2007. Enhancing evolution: the ethical case for making better people. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  37. ———. 2011. “Sparrows, hedgehogs and castrati: reflections on gender and enhancement.” Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (5): 262–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Hoag, H. 2008. “Sex on the Brain.” New Scientist 199 (2665): 28–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Hughes, J.H. 2004a. Citizen cyborg: why democratic societies must respond to the redesigned human of the future. Cambridge, MA : Westview Press.Google Scholar
  40. -----. 2004b. “Battle plan to be more than well: Transhumanism is finally getting in gear.” Trans humanity: Archive of the Content of the World Transhumanist Association website, 1998–2009. Accessed October 9, 2012. http://transhumanism.org/index.php/th/more/509/.
  41. Hurst, R. 2006. “The perfect crime.” In: Better humans? The politics of human enhancement and life extension, edited by P. Miller and J. Wilsdon, 114–121. London: Demos.Google Scholar
  42. Huxley, A. 1991. Brave new world. Harlow: Longman.Google Scholar
  43. Kaplan, D. 1993. “Prenatal screening and its impact on persons with disabilities.” Clinical Obstetrics and Gynecology 36 (3): 605–612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Kessler, S.J. 1998. Lessons from the intersexed. New Brunswick, New Jersey, and London: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Kevles, D.J. 1985. In the name of eugenics: genetics and the uses of human hereditary. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
  46. Kittay, E.F. 2006. “Thoughts on the desire for normality.” In Surgically shaping children: essays on technology, and the pursuit of normality, edited by E. Parens, 90–110. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Kitcher, P. 1996. The lives to come: the genetic revolution and human possibilities. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  48. Laqueur, T. 1990. Making sex: body and gender from the Greeks to Freud. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  49. McRuer, R. 2010 “Compulsory Able-bodiedness and Queer/Disabled Existence.” In The Disability Studies Reader, 3rd ed., edited by L. J. Davis, 383–392. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  50. McRuer, R, and A.L. Wilkerson. 2003. “Introduction: Cripping the (Queer) nation.” GLQ 9 (1–2): 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Mills, C. 2011. Futures of reproduction bioethics and biopolitics. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Mills, C. 2003. “The child’s right to an open future?” Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (4): 499–509.Google Scholar
  53. Nelson, J.L. 1998. “The meaning of the act: reflections on the expressive force of reproductive decision making and policies.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8 (2): 165–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. ———. 2000. “Prenatal diagnosis, personal identity, and disability.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 10 (3): 213–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Oliver, M. 2009. Understanding disability: from theory to practice, 2nd ed. Basingstoke England; New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  56. Parens, E., ed. 2006. Surgically shaping children: essays on technology, and the pursuit of normality. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press. Google Scholar
  57. Parens, E., and A. Asch. 1999. “The disability rights critique of prenatal genetic testing: reflections and recommendations.” The Hastings Centre Report 29 (5): 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. ———. eds. 2000. Prenatal testing and disability rights. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  60. Ponsonby, A-L., A. McMichael, and I. van der Mei. 2002. “Ultraviolet radiation and autoimmune disease: insights from epidemiological research.” Toxicology 181–182 [27 December]: 71–78.Google Scholar
  61. President's Council on Bioethics. 2003. Beyond Therapy: biotechnology and the pursuit of happiness. New York: Regan Books.Google Scholar
  62. Press, N. 2000. “Assessing the expressive character of prenatal testing: the choices made or the choices made available?” In Prenatal testing and disability rights, edited by E. Parens and A. Asch, 214–233. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
  63. Rose, N.S. 2007. The politics of life itself: biomedicine, power, and subjectivity in the twenty-first century. Princeton, NJ Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Salamon, G. 2010. Assuming a body: transgender and rhetorics of materiality. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  65. Savulescu, J. 2001. “Procreative beneficence: why we should select the best children.” Bioethics 15 (5): 413–426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. ———. 2002. “Deaf lesbians, ‘designer disability,’ and the future of medicine.” British Medical Journal 325: 771–775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. ———. 2005. “New breeds of humans: the moral obligation to enhance.”, Law and Moral Philosophy of Reproductive Biomedicine 1 (1): 36–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. ———. 2006. “Genetic interventions and the ethics of enhancement of human beings.” In The Oxford handbook on bioethics, edited by B. Steinbock, 516–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  69. ———. 2008. “Procreative beneficence: reasons not to have disabled children.” In The Sorting Society, edited by L. Skene and J. Thomson, 51–68. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  70. Savulescu, J., and N. Bostrom, eds. 2009. Human enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  71. Savulescu, J., and G. Kahane. 2009. “The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life.” Bioethics 23: 274–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Savulescu, J., R. ter Meulen, and G. Kahane, eds. 2011. Enhancing human capacities. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  73. Savulescu, J., A. Sandberg, and G. Kahane. 2011. “Well-being and enhancement.” In Enhancing Human Capacities, edited by J. Savulescu, R. ter Meulen, and G. Kahane, 3–18. Oxford Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  74. Saxton, M. 1997. “Disability rights and selective abortion.” In Abortion Wars: a half century of struggle, edited by Rickie Solinger, 374–393. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  75. Scully, J.L. 2008. Disability bioethics: moral bodies, moral difference. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
  76. Shakespeare, T. 2006. Disability rights and wrongs. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  77. Silver, L.M. 1999. Remaking Eden: cloning, genetic engineering and the future of human kind. London: Pheonix.Google Scholar
  78. Skene, L., and J. Thompson, eds. 2008. The sorting society: the ethics of genetic screening and therapy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Sparrow, R. 2007. “Procreative beneficence, obligation, and eugenics.” Genomics, Society, and Policy 3 (3): 43–59.Google Scholar
  80. ———. 2008a. “Genes, identity, and the expressivist critique.” In The Sorting Society, edited by L. Skene and J. Thomson, 111–132. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  81. ———. 2008b. “Is it ‘every man’s right to have babies if he wants them’? Male pregnancy and the limits of reproductive liberty.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 18 (3): 275–299. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. ———. 2010a. “Better than men? Sex and the therapy/enhancement distinction.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 20 (2): 115–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. ———. 2010b. “Should human beings have sex? Sexual dimorphism and human enhancement.” American Journal of Bioethics 10 (7): 3–12. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. ———. 2010c. “Liberalism and eugenics.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (3): 499–517. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. ———. 2010d. “Implants and ethnocide: learning from the cochlear implant controversy.” Disability and Society 25 (4): 455–466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. ———. 2011a. “Human enhancement and sexual dimorphism.” Bioethics 25: Online first. DOI:  10.1111/j.1467-8519.2011.01884.x.
  87. ———. 2011b. “Harris, harmed states, and sexed bodies.” Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (5): 276–279. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. ———. 2011c. “Fear of a female planet: how John Harris came to endorse eugenic social engineering.” Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (1): 4–7. DOI:  10.1136/jme.2011.045021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. ———. 2011d. “A not-so-new eugenics: Harris and Savulescu on human enhancement.” Hastings Center Report 41 (1): 32–42. Google Scholar
  90. ———. Forthcoming. “Ethics, eugenics, and politics.” In Toward Bioethics in 2050international dialogues, edited by A. Akayabashi.Google Scholar
  91. Stainton, T. 2003. “Identity, difference and the ethical politics of prenatal testing.” Journal of Intellectual Disability Research 47 (7): 533–539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Steinbock, B., and R. McClamrock. 1994. “When is birth unfair to the child?” Hastings Center Report 24: 15–21.Google Scholar
  93. Stock, G. 2003. Redesigning humans: choosing our children’s genes. London Profile Books.Google Scholar
  94. Strong, C. 2005. “Harming by conceiving: a review of misconceptions and a new analysis.” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30: 491–516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Sullivan, N., and S. Murray, eds. 2009. Somatechnics: queering the technologisation of bodies. Farnham, England; Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  96. Sumner, L.W. 1996. Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford University Press: New York. Google Scholar
  97. Warner, M. 1999. The trouble with normal: sex, politics, and the ethics of queer life. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  98. Wendell, S. 1996. The rejected body. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  99. Wikler, D. 1999. “Can we learn from eugenics?” Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (2): 183–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  100. Wilkerson, A.L. 1998. Diagnosis: difference; the moral authority of medicine. Ithaca: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  101. World Health Organisation. 2009. World health statistics 2009. Geneva: World Health Organisation.Google Scholar
  102. Yuen, A.W.C., and N.G. Jablonski. 2010. “Vitamin D: in the evolution of human skin colour.” Medical Hypotheses 74 (1): 39–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media New York 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy ProgramMonash UniversityClaytonAustralia

Personalised recommendations