Advertisement

In Defence of Activities

Article

Abstract

In this paper, we examine what is to be said in defence of Machamer, Darden and Craver’s (MDC) controversial dualism about activities and entities (Machamer, Darden and Craver’s in Philos Sci 67:1–25, 2000). We explain why we believe the notion of an activity to be a novel, valuable one, and set about clearing away some initial objections that can lead to its being brushed aside unexamined. We argue that substantive debate about ontology can only be effective when desiderata for an ontology are explicitly articulated. We distinguish three such desiderata. The first is a more permissive descriptive ontology of science, the second a more reductive ontology prioritising understanding, and the third a more reductive ontology prioritising minimalism. We compare MDC’s entities-activities ontology to its closest rival, the entities-capacities ontology, and argue that the entities-activities ontology does better on all three desiderata.

Keywords

Activities MDC Machamer, Darden and Craver Capacities Ontology Metaphysics of science Understanding Minimalism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to two anonymous referees for very helpful comments. This research was supported by The Leverhulme Trust and the UK Arts and Humanities Research Council.

References

  1. Adams, R. L. P., Knowler, J. T., & Leader, D. P. (1992). The biochemistry of the nucleic acids (11th ed.). London: Chapman and Hall.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1975). Causality and determination. In E. Sosa (Ed.), Causation and conditionals (pp. 63–81). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. In Studies in the history and philosophy of the biological and biomedical sciences, Vol. 36. pp. 421–441.Google Scholar
  4. Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  5. Cartwright, N. (2004). Causation: One word many things. Philosophy of Science, 71, 805–819.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries. Cambridge: CUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about biological mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 958–969.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. de Regt, H. (2004). Making sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 71(1), 98–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. de Regt, H. (2009). The epistemic value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 585–597.Google Scholar
  10. Dowe, P. (1995). Causality and conserved quantities: A reply to Salmon. Philosophy of Science, 62, 321–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dowes, E. A. (1980). Quantitative problems in biochemistry. NY: Longman Group Limited.Google Scholar
  12. Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Dupré, J., & O’Malley, M. (2012). Metagenomics and biological ontology reprinted in Dupré’: Processes of Life: Essays in the philosophy of biology (pp. 188–205), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Gillett, C. (2007). The metaphysics of mechanisms and the challenge of the new reductionism. In M. Schouten & H. L. de Jong (Eds.), The matter of the mind. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Gillett, C. (2008). The hidden battles over emergence. In P. Clayton (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of religion and science (pp. 801–818). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Glennan, S. (2005). Modeling mechanisms. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 443–464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2010). Function and organization: Comparing the mechanisms of protein synthesis and natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 279–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Illari, P. M., & Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanisms are real and local. In P. M. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Casuality in the sciences (pp. 818–844). Oxford: Oxford Uniuversity Press.Google Scholar
  20. Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18(1), 27–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Abingdon: Rutledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Persson, J. (2010). Activity-based accounts of mechanism and the threat of polygenic effects. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 135–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Psillos, S. (2004). A glimpse of the secret connexion: Harmonizing mechanisms with counterfactuals. Perspectives on Science College, 12(3), 288–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Quine, W. V. Q. (1948). On what there is. In Review of metaphysics, Vol. 2, pp. 21–38, reprinted in Crane and Farkas (Eds.) Metaphysics, 2004, Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  30. Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Existence and quantification. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Rescher, N. (1996). Process metaphysics: An introduction to process philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  32. Santos-Lleo, M., Schartel, N., Tananbaum, H., Tucker, W., & Weisskopf, M. C. (2009). The first decade of science with Chandra and XMM-Newton. Nature, 462, 24–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In V. Peter Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause (pp. 109–135). Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Shoemaker, S. (1984). Identity, cause, and mind: Philosophical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Skipper, R., & Millstein, R. (2005). Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 327–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Tabery, J. (2004). Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Torres, P. J. (2009). A modified conception of mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 71(2), 233–251 (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  38. Voet, D., & Voet, J. G. (2004). Biochemistry. NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
  39. Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  40. Whitford, D. (2005). Proteins: Structure and function. Sussex: John Wiley and Sons Ltd.Google Scholar
  41. Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). The ontology of complex systems. In His re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), S366–S377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University CollegeLondonUK
  2. 2.University of KentCanterburyUK

Personalised recommendations