General Relativity and Gravitation

, Volume 43, Issue 12, pp 3657–3664 | Cite as

The reasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences

Research Article


Mathematics and its relation to the physical universe have been the topic of speculation since the days of Pythagoras. Several different views of the nature of mathematics have been considered: Realism—mathematics exists and is discovered; Logicism—all mathematics may be deduced through pure logic; Formalism—mathematics is just the manipulation of formulas and rules invented for the purpose; Intuitionism—mathematics comprises mental constructs governed by self evident rules. The debate among the several schools has major importance in understanding what Eugene Wigner called, The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences. In return, this ‘Unreasonable Effectiveness’ suggests a possible resolution of the debate in favor of Realism. The crucial element is the extraordinary predictive capacity of mathematical structures descriptive of physical theories.


Philosophy of science History of science 


Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.


  1. 1.
    Wigner E.: Symmetries and Reflections. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN (1967)Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Bochner, S.: The Role of Mathematics in the Rise of Science, 4th edn. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ (1981). See p.v (Preface). The first edition was written in the mid sixtiesGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    London Philosophy Study Guide, University of London, NB Do not google the acronym LPSG to find the site
  4. 4.
    Neugebauer O.: The Exact Sciences in Antiquity, 2nd edn. Dover Publications, New York (1969)Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Allen, D.: Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans. (1997)
  6. 6.
    Klein J.: Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra, pp. 63–68. Dover Publications, New York (1992)Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Ross W.D.: Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book 1-Section 5. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1924)Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Galilei, G.: Il Saggiatore (The Assayer) (1623). Drake, S., O’Malley, C.D., translators, 1960, The Controversy on the Comets of 1618. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, PA (1960)Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Weyl, H.: Raum-Zeit-Materie, 5th edn. Springer-Verlag, Berlin (1923). See page 136. Translation furnished by E.L. Schucking, New York UniversityGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Körner, S.: The Philosophy of Mathematics—An Introductory Essay. Dover Publications, New York (1986). See the first paragraph of the Introduction. Chapter VIII, on the relationship between pure and applied mathematics, contains the material most closely relevant to this paperGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Everett, E.: This observation was uttered in an address at the inauguration of Washington University of St. Louis (1947)Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Hardy, G.H.: Mind, new series 38, 1–25 (1929)Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Frege G.: Foundations of Arithmetic, revised 2nd edn, pp. 99. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL (1986)Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Weber, H.: In a eulogy, (Jahresberichte Deutscher Matematiker-Vereinigung 2, 5–31, (1893)), cites a lecture by Kronecker before a session of the Berliner Naturforschung-Sammelung in 1886, in which Kronecker stated, “Die ganzen Zahlen hat der liebe Gott gemacht, alles andere ist Menschenwerk.”Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Whitehead A.N., Russell B.: Principia Mathematica, vol. 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1910)Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Quoted in N. Rose: Mathematical Maxims and Minims, Rome Press, Raleigh, NC (1988)Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Kleene, S.: Introduction to Metamathematics. (North-Holland, Amsterdam 1952 with corrections 1971, 10th reprint 1991), See in particular Chapter III: Critique of Mathematical Reasoning, sect. 13 IntuitionismGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Dirac P.A.M.: The Principles of Quantum Mechanics, 4th edn. revised, pp. 15. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1958)Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Dirac, P.A.M.: The Relativistic Wave Electron. European Conference on Particle Physics, Budapest (1977)Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Appell, P.: Sur une interprétation des valeurs imaginaires du temps en Mécanique, Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Scéances de l’Académie des Sciences 87(1), (1878)Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Dahaene S.: The Number Sense. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Hawking, S.W.: Gödel and the End of Physics. (2002)
  23. 23.
    Valenti, M.B.: The renormalization of charge and temporality in quantum electrodynamics (2008).
  24. 24.
    Neuenschwander D.E.: Does any piece of mathematics exist for which there is no application whatsoever in physics?. Am. J. Phys. 63, 1065 (1996)ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    de la Torre A.C., Zamora R.: Answer to Question #31. Am. J. Phys. 69, 103 (2001)ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    Gottlieb H.P.W.: Answer to Question #31. Am. J. Phys. 69, 103 (2001)MathSciNetADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Visiting ScholarNew York UniversityNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations