Skip to main content
Log in

Benefits of Objective Collapse Models for Cosmology and Quantum Gravity

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We display a number of advantages of objective collapse theories for the resolution of long-standing problems in cosmology and quantum gravity. In particular, we examine applications of objective reduction models to three important issues: the origin of the seeds of cosmic structure, the problem of time in quantum gravity and the information loss paradox; we show how reduction models contain the necessary tools to provide solutions for these issues. We wrap up with an adventurous proposal, which relates the spontaneous collapse events of objective collapse models to microscopic virtual black holes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Before moving on we would like to say something about the interpretation of objective collapse theories. As we mentioned before, the main motivation for the construction of these theories is to avoid the measurement problem. That is, to construct a theory without the standard probabilistic interpretation of the quantum state. However, if one removes the standard probabilistic interpretation, without substituting it by something else, one loses the ability to make predictions and to get in touch with the physical world (see [15, 16]). Therefore, objective collapse models require a new interpretation. One could think of interpreting the wave-function directly as physical, as Schrödinger initially intended. However, the fact that wave-functions of multi-particle systems live in configuration space is something that renders this option unattractive to many. An alternative, first presented in [17], is to interpret the theory as describing a physical field \(m(\mathbf {x},t)\), constructed as the expectation value of the mass density operator on the state characterizing the system (the relativistic version of this interpretation is discussed in [18]). Yet another option, proposed in [19] and used in [8], is to take the GRW collapses, which occur at precise space–time points, as the quantities on which physical descriptions should be based.

  2. These are usually taken to be the Bunch Davies vacuum, which is a state of the quantum field naturally associated with the early de Sitter phase of the accelerated expansion.

  3. Such statistical aspects include considerations about: i) an hypothetical ensemble of universes, ii) different space and time regions of our universe and (iii) distinct orientations of our observations and characterizations of the CMB. Issues regarding the assumed connection between the quantum and statistical aspects of our characterization of the objects of interest also need to be considered.

  4. In order to solve this problem within the standard account, one would need to hold that to allow the identifications described above it is necessary to invoke a further averaging over orientations, without which predictions are not reliable. The problem is that there is no justification whatsoever for this assumption.

  5. In the sense that only after the stochastic variables have been converted into quantities with definite numerical values would those operators become explicitly defined.

  6. See [36, 37] for a similar prediction from different assumptions.

  7. There is a view according to which one need not worry about information loss and unitarity breakdown simply because \(\mathcal{I }^+\), or space-like hypersurfaces approaching it, are no Cauchy hypersurfaces. If that is the case, the singularity (or a space-like hypersurfaces near it) represents an additional part of the boundary of space–time where the causal curves can end. This is, from the purely mathematical point of view, complete accurate and correct. However, the issue is how are the observers that witness the complete evaporation, of say, a very small black hole, to characterize what they see as their space–time in which the black hole has disappeared? What would they say regarding the evolution of the physical objects that for them represent the totality of what exist at a certain region they consider to be a Cauchy hypersurface? That means that at the effective level, that of the laws of physics as they observe them to hold, they must confront a problem: are the laws of evolution compatible with quantum unitarity or are they not?

  8. Quantum field theory is usually considered the essential language in which to handle quantum matter in a spacial relativistic context. In the regime where gravity becomes important, we also envision a quantum field theoretic treatment of matter fields but at the very fundamental level we envision some sort of quantum gravity theory, perhaps resembling some of the currently popular programs, but modified to include effects that at the more effective level look like dynamical reductions.

  9. As far as we are aware, Penrose was the first to argue for collapse to resolve the black hole information paradox.

  10. A study of a range of possibilities for a stochastic fundamental law of evolution is presented in [47]

  11. We would like to thank an anonymous referee for leading us to explore this issue in some detail.

References

  1. Perez, A., Sahlmann, H., Sudarsky, D.: On the quantum origin of the seeds of cosmic structure. Class. Quantum Gravity 23, 2317 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Bohm, D., Bub, J.: A proposed solution of the measurement problem in quantum mechanics by a hidden variable theory. Rev. Mod. Phys. 38, 453 (1966)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Pearle, P.: Reduction of the state vector by a nonlinear Schrödinger equation. Phys. Rev. D 13, 857 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Pearle, P.: Towards explaining why events occur. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 18, 489 (1979)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ghirardi, G., Rimini, A., Weber, T.: A model for a unified quantum description of macroscopic and microscopic systems. In: Accardi, A.L. (ed.) Quantum Probability and Applications, pp. 223–232. Springer, Heidelberg (1985)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  6. Ghirardi, G., Rimini, A., Weber, T.: Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys. Rev. D 34, 470 (1986)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Bassi, A., Lochan, K., Satin, S., Singh, T., Ulbricht, H.: Models of wave-function collapse, underlying theories, and experimental tests. Rev. Mod. Phys. 85, 471 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  8. Tumulka, R.: A relativistic version of the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber model. J. Stat. Phys. 125, 821 (2006)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  9. Bedingham, D.: Relativistic state reduction model. J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 306, 012034 (2011)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  10. Tumulka, R.: On spontaneous wave function collapse and quantum field theory. Proc. R. Soc. A 462, 1897 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Pearle, P.: Combining stochastic dynamical state-vector reduction with spontaneous localization. Phys. Rev. A 39, 2277–2289 (1989)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  12. Ghirardi, G., Pearle, P., Rimini, A.: Markov-processes in Hilbert-space and continuous spontaneous localization of systems of identical particles. Phys. Rev. A 42, 78–89 (1990)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Pearle, P.: Toward a relativistic theory of statevector reduction. In: Miller, A. (ed.) Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty, pp. 193–214. Plenum, New York (1990)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  14. Ghirardi, G., Grassi, R., Pearle, P.: Relativistic dynamical reduction models: General framework and examples. Found. Phys., J.S. Bell’s 60th birthday issue 20, 1271 (1990).

  15. Albert, D.: In: Clifton, R. (ed.) Perspectives on Quantum Reality: Non-relativistic, Relativistic, Field-Theoretic, pp. 81–92. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1996)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  16. Lewis, P.J., Stud: Interpreting spontaneous collapse theories. His. Phil. Mod. Phys. 36, 165–180 (2005)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Ghirardi, G., Grassi, R., Benatti, F.: Describing the macroscopic world: closing the circle within the dynamical reduction program. Found. Phys. 35, 5 (1995)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Bedingham, D., Dürr, D., Ghirardi, G., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: Matter density and relativistic models of wave function collapse. J. Stat. Phys. (2013), arXiv:1111.1425.

  19. Bell, J.S.: Are there quantum jumps? In: Kilminster, C.W. (ed.) Schrödinger: Centenary Celebration of a Polymath, pp. 109–123. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  20. García, G.L., Landau, S.J., Sudarsky, D.: Quantum origin of the primordial fluctuation spectrum and its statistics. Phys. Rev. D 88, 023526 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  21. Padmanabhan, T.: Structure Formation in the Universe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Weinberg, S.: Cosmology. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Mukhanov, V.: Physical Foundations of Cosmology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2005)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Sudarsky, D.: Shortcomings in the understanding of why cosmological perturbations look classical. Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 20, 509 (2011)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Diez-Tejedor, A., Sudarsky, D.: Towards a formal description of the collapse approach to the inflationary origin of the seeds of cosmic structure. JCAP 07, 045 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  26. Unanue, A.D., Sudarsky, D.: Phenomenological analysis of quantum collapse as source of the seeds of cosmic structure. Phys. Rev. D 78, 043510 (2008)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  27. Landau, S.J., Scoccola, C.G., Sudarsky, D.: Cosmological constraints on nonstandard inflationary quantum collapse models. Phys. Rev. D 85, 123001 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  28. Martin, J., Vennin, V., Peter, P.: Cosmological inflation and the quantum measurement problem. arXiv:1207.2086 [hep-th] (2012).

  29. Cañate, P., Pearle, P., Sudarsky, D.: Continuous spontaneous localization wave function collapse model as a mechanism for the emergence of cosmological asymmetries in inflation. Phys. Rev. D 87, 104024 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  30. Das, S., Lochan, K., Sahu, S., Singh, T.P.: Quantum to classical transition of inflationary perturbations: continuous spontaneous localization as a possible mechanism. Phys. Rev. D 87, 085020 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  31. Isham, C.J.: Canonical quantum gravity and the problem of time. gr-qc/9210011 (1992).

  32. Gambini, R., Porto, R.A., Pullin, J.: Realistic clocks, universal decoherence and the black hole information paradox. Phys. Rev. Lett. 93, 240401 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  33. Gambini, R., Porto, R.A., Pullin, J.: Fundamental decoherence from relational time in discrete quantum gravity: Galilean covariance. Phys. Rev. D 70, 124001 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  34. Hawking, S.: Particle creation by black holes. Commun. Math. Phys. 43, 199 (1975)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  35. Almheiri, A., Marolf, D., Polchinski, J., Sully, J.: Black holes: complementarity or firewalls? (2012) arXiv:1207.3123 .

  36. Braunstein, S. L.: Black hole entropy as entropy of entanglement or it’s curtains for the equivalence principle (2009) arXiv:0907.1190v1 [quant-ph].

  37. Braunstein, S.L., Pirandola, S., Zyczkowski, K.: Better late than never: information retrieval from black holes. Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 101301 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  38. Ashtekar, A., Bojowald, M.: Black hole evaporation: a paradigm. Class. Quantum Gravity 22, 3349 (2005)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  39. Pearle, P., Squires, E.: Bound-state excitation, nucleaon decay experiments, and models of wave-function collapse. Phys. Rev. Lett. 73, 1 (1994)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  40. Penrose, R.: The Road to Reality. Knopf, New York (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Penrose, R.: Time asymmetry and quantum gravity. In: Isham, C.J., Penrose, R., Sciama, D.W. (eds.) Quantum Gravity II, p. 244 (1981)

  42. Hawking, S.: Quantum black holes. In: Hawking, S., Penrose, R. (eds.) The Nature of Space and Time, pp. 37–60. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Callender, C.: Is time an illusion? Sci. Am. 302(3), 1–11 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Callender, C.: Shedding light on time. Philos. Sci. (Proc.) 67, S587 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Callender, C. (ed.): Time, Reality and Experience. Time, Reality and Experience. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Smolin, L.: The Life of the Cosmos. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1997)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  47. Bassi, A., Durr, D., Hinrichs, G.: Uniqueness of the equation for quantum state vector collapse. Phys. Rev. Lett. 111, 210401 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  48. Colin, S., Valentini, A.: Mechanism for the suppression of quantum noise at large scales on expanding space (2013). arXiv:1306.1579 [hep-th].

  49. Valentini, A.: Inflationary cosmology as a probe of primordial quantum mechanics. Phys. Rev. D 82, 063513 (2010)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  50. Valentini, A.: Hidden variables and the large-scale structure of spacetime. In: Craig, W.L., Smith, Q. (eds.) Einstein, Relativity and Absolute Simultaneity, pp. 125–155. Routledge, London (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Pinto-Neto, N., Fabris, J.C.: Quantum cosmology from the de Broglie–Bohm perspective. Class. Quantum Gravity 30, 143001 (2013)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  52. Pinto-Neto, N., Santos, G., Struyve, W.: Quantum-to-classical transition of primordial cosmological perturbations in de Broglie–Bohm quantum theory. Phys. Rev. D 85, 083506 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  53. Falciano, F., Pinto-Neto, N.: Scalar perturbations in scalar field quantum cosmology. Phys. Rev. D 79, 023507 (2009)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  54. Goldstein, S., Teufel, S.: Quantum spacetime without observers: ontological clarity and the conceptual foundations of quantum gravity. Physics Meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, pp. 275–289. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2001)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to acknowledge partial financial support from DGAPA—UNAM projects IN107412 (DS), IA400312 (EO), and CONACyT project 101712 (DS).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elias Okon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Okon, E., Sudarsky, D. Benefits of Objective Collapse Models for Cosmology and Quantum Gravity. Found Phys 44, 114–143 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-014-9772-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-014-9772-6

Keywords

Navigation