Advertisement

Foundations of Science

, Volume 17, Issue 4, pp 321–337 | Cite as

Abduction and Estimation in Animals

  • Woosuk Park
Article

Abstract

One of the most pressing issues in understanding abduction is whether it is an instinct or an inference. For many commentators find it paradoxical that new ideas are products of an instinct and products of an inference at the same time. Fortunately, Lorenzo Magnani’s recent discussion of animal abduction sheds light on both instinctual and inferential character of Peircean abduction. But, exactly for what reasons are Peirce and Magnani so convinced that animal abduction can provide us with a novel perspective? Inspired by Peirce’s and Magnani’s discussions of animal abduction, I propose to compare Peirce’s and Magnani’s views of animal abduction with the estimative power of non-human animals and humans, which was one of the internal senses in medieval psychology.

Keywords

Animal abduction Estimation Charles S. Peirce Avicenna Lorenzo Magnani Instinct Inference 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Anderson D. R. (1986) The evolution of Peirce’s concept of abduction. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 22(2): 145–164Google Scholar
  2. Anderson D. R. (1987) Creativity and the philosophy of C. S. Peirce. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  3. Avicenna (1952). Kitãb Al-Najt. In F. Rahman Avicenna’s Psychology (An English Translation of Kitãb Al-Najt, Book II, Chapter VI with Historico-Philosophical Notes and Textual Improvements on the Cairo Edition.). London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Barad J. (1995) Aquinas on the nature and treatment of animals. International Scholars Publications, San Francisco/LondonGoogle Scholar
  5. Black D. (1993) Estimation (Wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and psychological dimensions. Dialogue 32: 219–258CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Black D. (2000) Imagination and estimation: Arabic paradigms and western transformations. Topoi 19: 59–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brogaard B. (1999) Peirce on abduction and rational control. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35(1): 129–155Google Scholar
  8. Burks A. W. (1946) Peirce’s Theory of abduction. Philosophy of Science 13: 301–306CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Burton R. B. (2000) The problem of control in abduction. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 36(1): 149–156Google Scholar
  10. Cadwallader T. C. (1975) Peirce as an experimental psychologist. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 11: 167–186Google Scholar
  11. Capek M. (1954) James’s early criticism of the automaton theory. Journal of the History of Ideas 15: 260–279CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Colapietro V. (2003) The space of signs: C.S. Peirce’s critique of psychologism. In: Jacquette D. (eds) Philosophy, psychology, and psychologism. Kluwer, BostonGoogle Scholar
  13. Diamond S. (1974) Four hundred years of instinct controversy. Behavior Genetics 4: 237–252CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Fann K. T. (1970) Peirce’s theory of abduction. Martinus Nijhoff, The HagueCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Feibleman J. (1946) An introduction to Peirce’s philosophy, interpreted as a system. Harper & brothers, New York, LondonGoogle Scholar
  16. Frankfurt H. G. (1958) Peirce’s account of inquiry. The Journal of Philosophy 55: 588–592CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Girel M. (2003) The metaphysics and logic of psychology: Peirce’s reading of James’s principles. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39: 163–203Google Scholar
  18. Hoffman M. H. G. (1999) Problems with Peirce’s concept of abduction. Foundations of Science 4(3): 271–305CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. James W. (1879) Are we automata?. Mind 13: 1–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Klubertanz G. P. (1952) The discursive power: Sources and doctrine of the vis cogitativa according to St. Thomas Aquinas. The Modern Schoolman, St. Louis, MissouriGoogle Scholar
  21. Lisska A. J. (2009) A look at inner sense in aquinas: A long-neglected faculty psychology. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80: 1–19Google Scholar
  22. Lisska A. J. (2010) Deely, aquinas, and poinsot: How the intentionality of inner sense transcends the limits of empiricism. Semiotica 178(1/4): 135–167Google Scholar
  23. Magnani L. (2009) Abductive cognition. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds) (2007) Model-based reasoning in science, technology and medicine. Springer, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  25. McCarthy, E. (1976). Medieval light theory and optics and Duns Scotus’ treatment of light in D. 13 of book II of his commentary on the sentences. Ph.D. dissertation, City University of New York.Google Scholar
  26. Paavola S. (2005) Peircean abduction: Instinct or inference?. Semiotica 153(1/4): 131–154Google Scholar
  27. Park, W. (2011) On animal cognition: Before and after the beast-machine controversy (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  28. Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). In C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss (vols. I–VI) & A. W. Burks (vols. VII–VIII) (Eds.), Collected Papers, (vol. 8). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Rescher N. (1978) Peirce’s philosophy of science. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre DameGoogle Scholar
  30. Rosenfield, L. C. (1940, 1968). From beast-machine to man-machine. New and Enlarged Edition, New York: Octagon Books, Inc.Google Scholar
  31. Roth R. J. (1988) Anderson on Peirce’s concept of abduction: Further reflections. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 24(1): 131–139Google Scholar
  32. Sepper D. (1989) Descartes and the eclipse of imagination, 1618–1630. Journal of the History of Philosophy 27: 379–403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Shanahan T. (1986) The first moment of scientific inquiry: C. S. Peirce on the logic of abduction. Transactions of Charles S. Peirce Society 22(4): 450–466Google Scholar
  34. Sterrett S. G. (2002) Too many instincts: Contrasting philosophical views on intelligence in humans and non-humans. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 14: 39–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Thagard P. (2007) Abductive inference: From philosophical analysis to neural mechanisms. In: Feeney A., Heit E. (eds) Inductive reasoning: Experimental, developmental, and computational approaches. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 226–247Google Scholar
  36. Thagard, P. (2010). How brains make mental models. In L. Magnani et al. (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology, studies in computational intelligence (vol. 314, pp. 447–461). Berlin: SpringerGoogle Scholar
  37. Wolfson H. A. (1935) The internal senses in Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew philosophic texts. Harvard Theological Review 28(2): 69–133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Yaldir H. (2009) Ibn Sînâ (Avicenna) and René Descartes on the faculty of imagination. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17(2): 247–278CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Humanities and Social SciencesKorea Advanced Institute of Science and TechnologyDaejeonSouth Korea

Personalised recommendations