Skip to main content
Log in

Paneth’s epistemology of chemical elements in light of Kant’s Opus postumum

  • Published:
Foundations of Chemistry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Friedrich Paneth’s conception of “chemical element” has functioned as the official definition adopted by the International Union of Pure and Applied Chemistry since 1923. Paneth maintains a distinction between empirical and “transcendental” concepts of element; furthermore, chemical science requires fluctuation between the two. The origin of the empirical-transcendental split is found in Immanuel Kant’s classic Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787). The present paper examines Paneth’s foundational concept of element in light of Kant’s attempt, late in life, to revoke key distinctions made in his Critique, including that of regulative and constitutive functions of reason. In a section of his Opus postumum devoted to the “Transition from the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science to Physics,” Kant bends his philosophical system to address the newly emerging sciences of matter of his time. Specifically, he tried, without success, to develop the transcendental ground for microscale motions of bodies encountered in physical, electrical and chemical processes. Paneth’s discussion of chemical element does not take the Opus postumum into account, which is why it begins with a rejection of Kant’s rejection (in his earlier writings) of chemistry’s status as science. I make the case that Paneth’s definition of element effectively maintains something very like Kant’s critical separation of regulative and constitutive principles, while a advancing the concept of chemical science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kant made extensive additions and changes in his second edition of the Critique. I follow the standard A/B notation to indicate the pagination of first and second editions (Kant, 1929/1965), respectively.

  2. I thank Klaus Ruthenberg for his discussion (2009) of this passage vis-à-vis Paneth’s thought.

  3. A detailed discussion of how he came to this decision would take us far afield. See for example, Scerri (2005). We will instead consider the consequences of this choice.

  4. Among them, material, substance, stuff, and medium.

  5. Joseph E. Earley, personal communication, August 2012.

  6. Schwanken occurs in the conclusion of his article. The context of its introduction is discussed in depth in next section, below.

  7. For example, http://en.bab.la/dictionary/german-english/schwanken.

  8. Quantum theory established that the canonical variables of mechanics are not independent at subatomic scales, they are conjugate (Bohr 1958, 39).

  9. Bohr noted that “any attempt to trace the detailed course of a transition process would involve an uncontrollable exchange of energy between the atom and the measuring instruments which would completely disturb the very energy balance we set out to investigate” (Bohr 1958, 7).

  10. van Brakel’s extensive discussion of water and “polywater” at the interface of the manifest and scientific images of the world (van Brakel 2000) contains several interesting starting points, as does the Philosophy of Chemistry Handbook (Hendry et al. 2011) and Scerri’s collected essays on the periodic table (Scerri 2008).

  11. For example, Friedman and Nordmann (2006), van Brakel (2006), Nielsen and Andersen (2007).

  12. This is a significant claim that bears further examination. At its most general level, beyond its application to Kant’s philosophy, this perspective is consonant with my understanding of the scale and range of metaphor’s efficacy in science. Metaphor is here presented as a mode of thinking, what Wu calls “metaphoring.” (Wu 2001).

References

  • Aston, F.W., Baxter, G.P., Brauner, B., Debierne, A., Leduc, A., Richards Soddy, T.W.F., Urbain, G.: Report of the international committee on the elements. J. Am. Chem. Soc. 45, 867–874 (1923)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N.: Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. Wiley, NY (1958)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N.: Essays 1958–1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. Richard Clay & Co., Suffolk (1963)

  • Earley Sr., J.E.: How chemistry shifts horizons: element, substance, and the essential. Found. Chem. 11, 65–77 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Förster, E., Rosen, M.: (transl. and eds.) Kant’s Opus postumum. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

  • Friedman, M., Nordmann, A.: The Kantian Legacy in 19th century science, MIT, Boston (2006)

  • Friedman, M.: Kant and the Exact Sciences. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.: In: Förster, E. (ed.) Opus postumum, trans. Förster, E., Rosen, M. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

  • Kant, I.: Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. St. Martin’s Press, New York (1929/1965)

  • Körner, S.: On Kant’s conception of science and the critique of practical reason. Kantstudien 82, 173–178 (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lequan, M.: La chimie selon Kant. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, K., Andersen, H.: The influence of Kant’s philosophy on the young H. C. Ørsted. In: Brain, R.M., Cohen, R.S., Knudsen, O. (eds.) Hans Christian Ørsted and the Romantic Legacy in Science, pp. 97–114. Springer, NY (2007)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paneth, F.A. The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 13, 1–14, 144–160 (1962) (reprinted in Foundations of Chemistry, 5, 2003, 113–145. Kluwer, The Netherlands)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruthenberg, K.: Friedrich Adolf Paneth (1887–1958). Hyle 3, 103–106 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruthenberg, K.: Paneth, Kant, and the philosophy of chemistry. Found. Chem. 11, 79–91 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.R.: Realism, reduction and the ‘intermediate position’. In: Bhushan, N., Rosenfeld, S. (eds.) Of Minds and Molecules, pp. 51–72. Oxford University Press, NY (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.R.: Some aspects of the metaphysics of chemistry and the nature of the elements. Hyle 11, 127–145 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W.: “Philosophy and the scientific image of man,” In: Colodny, R., (ed.) In Frontiers of Science and Philosophy, U. of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA (1962)

  • van Brakel, J.: Philosophy of Chemistry. Leuven University Press, Leuven (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • van Brakel, J.: Kant’s legacy for the philosophy of chemistry. In: Baird, J.D., et al. (eds.) Philosophy of Chemistry, pp. 69–91. Springer, Netherlands (2006)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, K.-m.: On Metaphoring: A Cultural Hermeneutic. Brill, Boston (2001)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Farzad Mahootian.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mahootian, F. Paneth’s epistemology of chemical elements in light of Kant’s Opus postumum . Found Chem 15, 171–184 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-013-9182-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-013-9182-4

Keywords

Navigation