Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Blameworthiness and the Reactive Attitudes

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I present and defend a novel version of the Reactive Attitude account of moral blameworthiness. In Section 1, I introduce the Reactive Attitude account and outline Allan Gibbard’s version of it. In Section 2, I present the Wrong Kind of Reasons Problem, which has been at the heart of much recent discussion about the nature of value, and explain why a reformulation of it causes serious problems for versions of the Reactive Attitude account such as Gibbard’s. In Section 3, I consider some ways in which Gibbard might attempt to avoid the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem. I argue that all of these ways fail to achieve their aim and further contend that the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem cannot be solved in a sufficiently convincing manner by the widely used method of making ad hoc distinctions among kinds of properties, kinds of attitudes, and kinds of reasons. In Section 4, I sketch my own version of the Reactive Attitude account of moral blameworthiness and show that it simply avoids the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem rather than attempting to solve the problem on a piecemeal basis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See especially Gibbard (1990: Chapter 7), Wallace (1994: Chapter 2) and Greenspan (1995).

  2. See also, e.g., Strawson (1962), Blackburn (1993 and 1998, especially Chapter 1). and Wallace (1994, 2006).

  3. Especially, Analysis, Ethics, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, and Philosophical Quarterly.

  4. A very partial list of works relevant to this topic includes Scanlon (1998: esp., Chapter 2, 2002), Crisp (1999, 2000, 2005, 2006, 2008), Dancy (2000a, 2000b, 2004: Chapter 9 - 12), D’Arms and Jacobson (2000), Parfit (2001a, Forthcoming), Zimmerman (2001, 2007), Wallace (2002), Stratton-Lake (2003a, 2003b, 2005), Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen (2004, 2005), Olson (2004, 2006), Suikkanen (2005), Heuer (2006), Stratton-Lake and Hooker (2006), Vayrynen (2006), Danielsson and Olson (2007), Skorupski (2007), Brannmark (2008), Rønnow-Rasmussen (2008). Ewing (1947: Chapter 5) is often taken as a precursor of this view. Korsgaard (1983) and Lemos (1994) are also useful.

  5. On reflection, the relevance of the Wrong Kind of Reason problem to the RA account should not be a surprise. This style of objection in which an unlikely confluence of events gives rise to justification, a practical reason, etc., is, of course, often the bane of bi-conditional analyses. One need only think of the classic paper by Gettier (1963) in which Ayer’s analysis of knowledge is foiled because both job candidates, Smith and Jones, just happen to have the same number of coins in their pockets. Among those who see the relevance of the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem for Gibbard, D’Arms and Jacobson (2000) are notable for the depth of their insights.

  6. In what follows, I focus on false negative cases. However, I turn to false positive cases in Section 4.

  7. In this passage, Gibbard is primarily concerned with moral wrongness, rather than moral blameworthiness. However, following Gibbard on this point would make the discussion much more complicated without adding any value. Nothing critical turns my on refocusing the passage moral blameworthiness.

  8. Gibbard sometimes speaks of anger where resentment seems more appropriate.

  9. The tracking metaphor is my own, not Gibbard’s. However, I was thinking here of a kind of analogy of the epistemology of Robert Nozick (1983).

  10. It is worth noting that others have attempted to use a double-tracking solution as a response to something similar to the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem in the literature on rational irrationality. See Kavka (1983) and Parfit (1984, 2001a). However, more recent work (2011b) as well as personal correspondence suggests that Parfit might have given up on it.

  11. To the best of my knowledge, the demon was first introduced into this literature by Crisp (1999).

  12. I am assuming for the purpose of this example that the proper domain of agents for whom it ought to make sense to feel resentment is Cleopatra’s court. As already noted, Gibbard is quite vague about the proper domain, but this fact does not have any relevance here since whatever the proper domain D is, we can always imagine that the demon’s threat extends to all members of D.

  13. Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen (2004).

  14. In explaining why this is so, I focus on Cleopatra and guilt in order to keep the discussion manageable, but essentially the same points can be made about the other members of her court and resentment.

  15. As per Frankfurt (1971).

  16. In order to prevent the cases from getting out of hand, I won’t assign this modification of the circumstances a separate case number. However, readers who wish to pick it out for discussion might refer to it as Case 3*.

  17. We can safely ignore the non-identity problem for the purposes of this thought experiment.

  18. In the rest of this paper, I take it as a given that Gibbard’s version of the RA account has been shown to be false by the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem.

  19. I borrow talk of conforming to reasons from Raz (2009), though I do not wish to imply that he would agree with the way in which I develop this idea.

  20. On counting in favor of, see Scanlon (1998: Chapter 1). I adopt the language of contributory and perfect reasons from Dancy (2004) and Broome (2004) respectively.

  21. One astute observer pointed out that in Case 5 it seems like I am endorsing the moral permissibility of capital punishment! However, that is not my intention, and this is simply an artifact of Gibbard’s original example. Changing the case to avoid this artifact would be too tedious to warrant doing so in these circumstances.

  22. Certainly, it might provide me with reason to feel other emotions, including shame, embarrassment, or disappointment. But none of this provides the resources needed for generating a counterexample to my version of the RA account.

  23. Again, the specifics of this example are not very important. Some hold a normative theory in which it is always wrong to break one’s promise. The illustration which I offer here will not convince such a person. But she is free to imagine another set of circumstances in which there are morally salient reasons both for and against doing a certain action even though the balance of reasons clearly tips in one direction or the other.

  24. I am grateful to audience members at a talk given at the University of Reading, the Universityof Calgary, and the City University of New York (Lehman College) among other places for the their insightful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Blackburn S (1993) Essays on quasi-realism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn S (1998) Ruling passions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brannmark J (2008) Excellence and means: on the limits of buck—passing. J Value Inq 42:301–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2004) Reasons. In: Wallace RJ et al (eds) Reasons and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R (1999) Review of Kupperman, value...and what follows. Philosophy 75

  • Crisp R (2005) Value, reasons, and the structure of justification. Analysis 65:80–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2006) Reasons and the good. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2008) Goodness and reasons: accentuating the negative. Mind 117:257–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2000) Contractualism and the good. Philos Books 41:235–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (2000) Should we pass the buck? In: O’Hear A (ed) Philosophy, the good, the true and the beautiful. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (2004) Ethics without principles. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Danielsson S, Olson J (2007) Brentano and buck-passers. Mind 116:511–522

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms J, Jacobson D (2000) Sentiment and value. Ethics 110:722–748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewing AC (1947) The definition of good. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt H (1971) Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68:5–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier E (1963) Is knowledge justified true belief? Analysis 23:121–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1990) Wise choices, apt feelings. Harvard Belknap, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan P (1995) Practical guilt: Moral dilemmas, emotions, and social norms. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heuer U (2006) Explaining reasons: where does the buck stop? Journal of Ethics and Soc Phil 1

  • Kavka G (1983) The toxin puzzle. Analysis 43:33–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard C (1983) Two distinctions in goodness. Philos Rev 92:169–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemos N (1994) Intrinsic value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1981) Philosophical explanations. Harvard Belknap, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson J (2004) Buck-passing and the wrong kind of reasons. Philos Q 54:295–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson J (2006) G.E. Moore on goodness and reasons. Australas J Philos 84:525–534

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Claredon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (2001) Reasons and rationality. In: Egonsson D et al (eds) Exploring practical philosophy: From action to values. Aldershot, Ashgate

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (2011b). On What Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Rabinowicz W, Rønnow-Rasmussen T (2004). The strike of the demon. Ethics 114

  • Rabinowicz W, Rønnow-Rasmussen T (2005) Buck-passing and the right kind of reasons. Philos Q 55

  • Raz J (2009) Between authority and interpretation. Oxford University Press: Oxford

  • Rønnow-Rasmussen T (2008) Buck-passing personal values. In: Chan D (ed) Moral psychology today: Values, rational choice and the will. Springer, Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard Belknap, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski J (2007) Buck-Passing about Goodness. In: Rønnow-Rasmussen, T (ed) Philosophical papers dedicated to Wlodek. <http://www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek/site/papper/SkorupskiJohn.pdf> Accessed November 2007

  • Stratton-Lake P (2003b) Scanlon, permission, and redundancy. Analysis 67

  • Stratton-Lake, P (2003a) Scanlon’s contractualism and the redundancy objection. Analysis 67

  • Stratton-Lake P (2005) How to deal with evil demons. Ethics 115

  • Stratton-Lake P, Hooker B (2006) Scanlon versus Moore on goodness. In: Horgan T, Timmons M (eds) Meta-ethics after Moore. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson P (1962) Freedom and resentment. In: Freedom and resentment and other Essays. Methuen: London

  • Suikkanen J (2005) Reasons and value: In Defense of the Buck-Passing Account. Ethical Theory and Moral Pract 7

  • Vayrynen P (2006) Resisting the buck-passing account of value. Oxford Stud in Meta-Ethics 1

  • Wallace R (1994) Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (2002) Scanlon’s contractualism. Ethics 112

  • Wallace R (2006) Normativity and the will. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman M (2001) The nature of intrinsic value. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman M (2007) The good and the right. Utilitas 19

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leonard Kahn.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kahn, L. Moral Blameworthiness and the Reactive Attitudes. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 14, 131–142 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-010-9249-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-010-9249-4

Keywords

Navigation