Skip to main content
Log in

Information Exchange and Transnational Environmental Problems

  • Published:
Environmental and Resource Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper analyzes information exchange in a model of transnational pollution control in which countries use private information in independently determining their domestic environmental policies. We show that countries may not always have an incentive to exchange their private information. However, for a sufficiently high degree of predictability of domestic environmental policy processes, the expected welfare from sharing information is greater than the expected welfare from keeping it private. The minimum degree of policy predictability for which information sharing occurs increases with the level of environmental risk. Intuitively, information exchange can help mitigate the perception of global uncertainty (both political and scientific) that surrounds transnational environmental problems and potentially improve welfare if policymaking processes are sufficiently aligned with evidence-based approaches (predictable).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for instance Holland et al. (2014), Heal (2008), Hulme (2009), Milman and Ray (2011), Parson and Zeckhauser (1993), Gamman (1994), Salehyan and Hendrix (2010), Buhr and Freedman (2001), Haffoudhi (2005), Shock (2004), Drutman (2010), Pielke (2005, 2006), Washington and Cook (2011), Shock (2004), Cairns (1992), Sachs (2008).

  2. In USA, lobbying and political contributors are not required to disclose the particular issues for which their contributions are targeted.

  3. The predictability of the policymaking process is inextricably linked to transparency and accountability issues. The paper by Juni (2000) discusses factors that may affect transparency in environmental policy making processes.

  4. The paper by Espinola-Arredondo and Munoz-Garcia (2011) looks at the management of information in a common pool resource where an incumbent has complete information on the stock while the entrant has incomplete information.

  5. In solving the model in Sect. 3, we will focus on the case where \(N=2\) (two countries).

  6. We thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this possibility.

  7. For instance, each country benefits from burning fossil fuels to run its economy.

  8. Accounting for private information in the process of making regulations should be an integral part of the study of the political economy of environmental policy (Millner and Ollivier 2016).

  9. Thank you to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

  10. See for instance (Holland et al. 2014; Heal 2008; Hulme 2009; Milman and Ray 2011; Parson and Zeckhauser 1993; Gamman 1994; Salehyan and Hendrix 2010; Buhr and Freedman 2001; Haffoudhi 2005; Shock 2004; Drutman 2010; Pielke 2005, 2006; Washington and Cook 2011; Shock 2004; Cairns 1992; Sachs 2008).

  11. Note that this is not equivalent to each country facing the same domestic constraints, \(\mathbf X ^{i}\), on the level of stringency since the values of \(\mathbf X \) are indexed by i.

  12. For instance, the parliament in each country can write up a bill to control the domestic amount of pollution. The process of transforming an idea into legislative language is typically an interactive, behind-the-scenes process that can take into account some political factors that are not publicly known.

  13. The conditional probability \(P\left( \widetilde{s}^{i}=s^{i}_{L}\Big |\widetilde{\upbeta }={\upbeta }_{H}\right) \) or \(P\left( \widetilde{s}^{i}=s^{i}_{H}\Big |\widetilde{\upbeta }={\upbeta }_{L}\right) \) may be thought of as the likelihood that policymaking processes are not aligned with evidence-based approaches (predictability). For instance, the expression \(P\left( \widetilde{s}^{i}=s^{i}_{L}\Big |\widetilde{\upbeta }={\upbeta }_{H}\right) \) would represent the likelihood that the private information that drives the policymaking process is not aligned with an evidence-based approach (predictability) that supports a stringent stance on transnational environmental problems.

  14. Note that this implies that both countries are identical ex ante.

  15. In a model where private the signal is first observed before information exchange decision is made, a country can possibly send a noisy signal to another country, therefore allowing an environment in which individual countries can strategically manipulate the information that is being shared.

  16. The effect of predictability on the policy outcomes may be thought of as a form of rational expectations.

  17. By worst case scenarios, we refer to an asymptotic analysis where the level of uncertainty ( say variance) on the damage parameter grows large, which can also be thought off as the limiting case where the ratio \(\frac{{\upbeta }_{H}}{{\upbeta }_{L}}\) is very large.

  18. In the climate agreement reached in Paris in December 2015, it is expected that countries will continue to include more transparent and evidence-based approaches in their domestic policymaking processes (Dimitrov 2016).

References

  • Aldy J, Pizer W, Tavoni RL, Akimoto MK, Blanford G, Carraro C, Clarke L, Edmonds J, Iyer G, McJeon H, Richels R, Rose S, Sano F (2016) Economic tools to promote transparency and comparability in the Paris Agreement. Nat Clim Change 11:1000–1004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim G (2010) Strategic use of environmental information. Environ Resour Econ 46:207–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennear L, Olmstead S (2008) The impacts of the “right to know” : information disclosure and the violation of drinking water standards. J Environ Econ Manag 56:117–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buhr N, Freedman M (2001) Culture, institutional factors and differences in environmental disclosure between Canada and the United States. Crit Perspect Account 12:293–322

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabrera A, Cabrera E (2002) Knowledge-sharing dilemmas. Organ Stud 23:687–710

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cairns R (1992) Natural resources and Canadian federalism: decentralization, recurring conflict, and resolution. Publius 22:55–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen M, Santhakumar V (2007) Information disclosure as environmental regulation: a theoretical analysis. Environ Resour Econ 37:599–620

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dimitrov S (2016) The Paris Agreement on climate change: behind closed doors. Glob Environ Polit 16:1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dovi S (2014) The ethics of the revolving door. Georget J Law Public Policy 12:535

    Google Scholar 

  • Drutman L (2010) The business of America is lobbying: explaining the growth of corporate political activity in Washington, DC, Ph.D. thesis, University of California, Berkeley, CA, US

  • Espinola-Arredondo A, Munoz-Garcia F (2011) Can incomplete information lead to under-exploitation in the commons? J Environ Econ Manag 62:402–413

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan-Watson B, Elliott B, Watson T (2015) Lobbying by trade associations on EU climate policy. Technical report. Policy Studies Institute

  • Fearon J (1997) Signaling foreign policy interests: tying hands versus sinking costs. J Confl Resolut 41:68–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gamman J (1994) Overcoming obstacles in environmental policy making: creating partnerships through mediation. State University of New York Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gullberg A (2008) Lobbying friends and foes in climate policy: the case of business and environmental interest groups in the European Union. Energy Policy 36:2964–2972

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haffoudhi H (2005) Political-support lobbies responses to international environmental agreements, Cahiers de la maison des sciences economiques, Université Panthéon-Sorbonne (Paris 1)

  • Heal G (2008) Environmental politics. In: Michel-Kerjan E, Slovic P (eds) The irrational economist: future directions in behavioral economics and risk management. Public Affairs Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland S, Hughes J, Knittel C, Parker N (2014) Some inconvenient truths about climate change policy: the distributional impacts of transportation policies. Rev Econ Stat 97:1052–1069

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hulme M (2009) Why we disagree about climate change: understanding controversy, inaction and opportunity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Juni R (2000) Decision-making processes in environmental policy and regulation. Palgrave Macmillan UK, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kang K (2016) Policy influence and private returns from lobbying in the energy sector. Rev Econ Stud 83:269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulsum A (2012) Getting to green : a sourcebook of pollution management policy tools for growth and competitiveness, working paper 71608, World Bank

  • Leiserowitz A (2005) American risk perceptions: is climate change dangerous? Risk Anal 25:1433–1442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millner A, Ollivier H (2016) Beliefs, politics, and environmental policy. Rev Environ Econ Policy 10:226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milman A, Ray I (2011) Interpreting the unknown: uncertainty and the management of transboundary groundwater. Water Int 36:631–645

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oleszek W (2011) Congressional lawmaking: a perspective on secrecy and transparency. Technical report, Congressional Research Service, Washsington, DC

  • Parkhurst J (2017) The politics of evidence: from evidence-based policy to the good governance of evidence. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Parson E, Zeckhauser R (1993) Equal measures and fair burdens: negotiating environmental treaties in an unequal world, discussion paper e-93-03. Harvard University, Kennedy School of Government

  • Pielke R (2005): Accepting politics in science. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/articles/A61928-2005Jan9.html

  • Pielke R (2006) When scientists politicize science. Regulation 29:28–34. http://www.cato.org/pubs/regulation/regv29n1/v29n1-4.pdf

  • Potters J, Van Winden F (1990) Modeling political pressure as transmission of information. Eur J Polit Econ 6:61–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogelj J, McCollum D, Reisinger A, Meinshausen M, Riahi K (2013) Probabilistic cost estimates for climate change mitigation. Nature 493:79–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sachs J (2008) Common wealth: economics for a crowded planet. Penguin Press HC, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Salehyan I, Hendrix C (2010) Science and the international politics of climate change. J Dipl XI:27–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Shock D (2004) A typology of interest group behavior during the implementation of environmental policy in Canada and the United States, technical report, Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Southern Political Science Association. http://www.allacademic.com/meta/p67715_index.html

  • Stavins R (2011) The problem of the commons: still unsettled after 100 years. Am Econ Rev 101:81–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutcliffe S, Court J (2005) Evidence-based policy making: what is it? How does it work? What relevance for developing countries. Overseas Development Institute, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson A (2006) Management under anarchy: the international politics of climate change. Clim Change 78:7–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • UCS (2012) A climate of corporate control: how corporations have influenced the U.S. dialogue on climate science and policy

  • Vives (2008) Information sharing among firms, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, second edition

  • Washington H, Cook J (2011) Climate change denial: heads in the sand. Earthscan, Abingdon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the Editor and two anonymous referees for insightful and constructive suggestions. We appreciate helpful comments from Billy Pizer, Suzanne Dovi, Laura Evans, Steve Van Evera, Peter Maniloff, Brice Nguoghia, Matthew Platt, Quinn Weninger, Abdoul Sam, Charles F. Mason, and Claudia Bradley. We also thank participants at the 2012 Voluntary Pollution Control (VPC) Workshop in Ohio, the 2012 International EcoSummit in Ohio, and the 2012 Southern Economic Association Conference in New Orleans. All remaining errors are our own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johnson Kakeu.

Appendices

Appendix A: Expression of Probabilities in Eqs. (17) and (18)

Using the Bayes’ rule, The conditional probability of \({\upbeta }_{L}\) given the private signal \(s_{L}^{1}\) is computed as:

$$\begin{aligned} P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L}^{1})= & {} \frac{P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}^{1})}{P({\upbeta }_{L})},\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{L})P ({\upbeta }_{L})+P(s_{L}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{H})P({\upbeta }_{H})}, \nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{L})P ({\upbeta }_{L})+\left[ 1-P(s_{H}^{1}|{\upbeta }_{H})\right] P({\upbeta }_{H})}, \nonumber \\= & {} \frac{\frac{1}{2}\upsigma }{\frac{1}{2}\upsigma +\frac{1}{2}(1-\upsigma )},\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{\frac{1}{2}\upsigma }{\frac{1}{2}},\nonumber \\= & {} \upsigma . \end{aligned}$$
(35)

The conditional probability of \({\upbeta }_{H}\) given the private signal \(s_{L}^{1}\) is computed by using the complement rule for conditional probabilities:

$$\begin{aligned} P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{L}^{1})=1-P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L}^{1})=1-\upsigma . \end{aligned}$$
(36)

Using the multiplication rule (or chain rule) for conditional probabilities, the joint probability \(P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}^{2}|s_{L}^{1})\) is computed as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}^{2}|s_{L}^{1})= & {} \frac{P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}^{2},s_{L}^{1})}{P(s_{L}^{1})}\end{aligned}$$
(37)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1},s_{L}^{2},{\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1})},\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1},s_{L}^{2}|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1})}\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1})|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})P(s_{L}^{2}|{\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1})}\nonumber \\&\qquad (since\,s_{L}^{1}\,and\,s_{L}^{2}\,are\,conditionally\,independent\,given\, {\upbeta }_{L}),\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P(s_{L}^{1},{\upbeta }_{L})P(s_{L}^{2}|{\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1})},\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L}^{1})P(s_{L}^{1})P(s_{L}^{2}|{\upbeta }_{L})}{P(s_{L}^{1})},\nonumber \\= & {} P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L}^{1})P(s_{L}^{2}|{\upbeta }_{L}),\nonumber \\= & {} \upsigma \upsigma ,\nonumber \\= & {} \upsigma ^{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(38)

The computation of the following conditional probabilities follows the same reasoning.

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{H}^{2}|s_{L}^{L})=\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{L}^{2}|s_{L}^{1})=(1-\upsigma )^{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{H}^{2}|s_{L}^{1})=\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}^{2}|s_{H}^{1})=(1-\upsigma )\upsigma ,\\ P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{H}^{2}|s_{H}^{1})=(1-\upsigma )^{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{L}^{2}|s_{H}^{1})=\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{H}^{2}|s_{H}^{1})=\upsigma ^{2}.\\ \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(39)

Note also that \(P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{H})=1-\upsigma \) and \(P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{H})=\upsigma \)

Appendix B: Expression of Probabilities in the First Order Eq. (29)

Using the Bayes’ rule, the conditional probability \(P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L},s_{L})\) is computed as

$$\begin{aligned} P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L},s_{L})= & {} \frac{ P(s_{L},s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})}{ P(s_{L},s_{L})}, \end{aligned}$$
(40)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{ P(s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})P(s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})P ({\upbeta }_{L})}{ P(s_{L},s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})P({\upbeta }_{L})+P(s_{L},s_{L}| {\upbeta }_{H})P({\upbeta }_{H})} , \end{aligned}$$
(41)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{ P(s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})^{2}P({\upbeta }_{L})}{ P(s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{L})^{2} P({\upbeta }_{L})+P(s_{L}|{\upbeta }_{H})^{2}P({\upbeta }_{H})}, \end{aligned}$$
(42)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{\frac{1}{2}\upsigma ^{2}}{\frac{1}{2}\upsigma ^{2}+\frac{1}{2}(1-\upsigma )^{2}}, \end{aligned}$$
(43)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \frac{\upsigma ^{2}}{\upsigma ^{2}+(1-\upsigma )^{2}} , \end{aligned}$$
(44)

A similar reasoning is used to compute the following probabilities:

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{L},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{H},s_{L})=\frac{1}{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{L}|s_{H},s_{H})=\frac{(1-\upsigma )^{2}}{\upsigma ^{2}+(1-\upsigma )^{2}},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{L},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{L},s_{L})=\frac{(1-\upsigma )^{2}}{\upsigma ^{2}+(1-\upsigma )^{2}},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{H},s_{L})=\frac{1}{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H}|s_{H},s_{H})=\frac{\upsigma ^{2}}{\upsigma ^{2}+(1-\upsigma )^{2}}.\\ \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(45)

Appendix C: Expression of Probabilities in the Expected Welfare Eqs. (23) and (32)

$$\begin{aligned} P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L},s_{L})=P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L}|s_{L})P(s_{L})=\frac{1}{2}\upsigma ^{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(46)

Following the same reasoning, the following probabilities are computed:

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{H},s_{L})=\frac{1}{2}\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{L},s_{L})=\frac{1}{2}(1-\upsigma )^{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{H},s_{L})=\frac{1}{2}\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{L},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2}(1-\upsigma )\upsigma ,\\ P({\upbeta }_{L},s_{H},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2}(1-\upsigma )^{2},\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{L},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2}\upsigma (1-\upsigma ),\\ P({\upbeta }_{H},s_{H},s_{H})=\frac{1}{2}\upsigma ^{2}. \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(47)

Appendix D: The Value of Information Sharing

The value of information sharing is given by:

$$\begin{aligned}&E\left[ \widetilde{V}_{sharing}(e_{ij},\widetilde{\upbeta })\right] -E\left[ \widetilde{V}_{no\,sharing}(e_{i})\right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\frac{\upsigma ^{2}}{2}\left[ e_{LL}+e_{HH}-\frac{(1+\upalpha )^2}{2} ({\upbeta }_{L} e_{LL}^{2}+{\upbeta }_{H} e_{HH}^2)\right] \nonumber \\&\qquad + \frac{(1-\upsigma )^{2}}{2}\left[ e_{LL}+e_{HH}-\frac{(1+\upalpha )^2}{2} ({\upbeta }_{L} e_{HH}^{2}+{\upbeta }_{H} e_{LL}^{2})\right] \nonumber \\&\qquad + \upsigma (1-\upsigma )\left[ 2e_{LH}-\frac{(1+\upalpha )^2}{2}({\upbeta }_{L} +{\upbeta }_{H}) e_{LH}^{2})\right] -\log \left( \frac{1}{\upsigma }\right) \nonumber \\&\qquad - \frac{(1-\upalpha ^2)}{4}\left[ \upsigma ({\upbeta }_{L}e^2_{L}+{\upbeta }_{H}e^2_{H}) + (1-\upsigma )( {\upbeta }_{L}e^2_{H} +{\upbeta }_{H}e^2_{L}) \right] -\log \left( \frac{1}{\upsigma }\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(48)

where \(e_{LL},\,e_{LH}\) and \(e_{HH}\) are given by Eq. (30) while \(e_{L}\) and \(e_{H}\) are given by Eqs. (20)–(21).

Appendix E: Graph of the Value of Information Sharing, with \(\upalpha =1\)

As shown in Fig. 3 above, the value of information sharing can take either a positive or a negative sign depending on the values taken by the level of riskiness of the environmental damage and the degree of predictability of the environmental policy. This suggests that sharing information or keeping it private are plausible outcomes that may occur in analyzing information exchange in transnational environmental problems.

Fig. 3
figure 3

The value of information sharing drawn on the \(\left( {\upbeta }_{H}/ \upbeta _{H} \,,\,\upsigma \right) \) plane, with \(\upalpha =1\) and \({\upbeta }_{L}=0.3\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kakeu, J., Johnson, E.P. Information Exchange and Transnational Environmental Problems. Environ Resource Econ 71, 583–604 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-017-0174-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-017-0174-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation