Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The law and economics of sycophancy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Tullock (in: Rowley (ed) The selected works of Gordon Tullock, Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, pp 399–455, 2005) was skeptical of the presumed economic efficiency of the common law, as adversarialism, apparently inherent to common law procedures, allowed for and was prone to litigiousness. Common law litigations accord to patterns of rent-seeking, as litigants invest ever more resources to assure victory. This paper asks if viable institutional solutions can emerge to resolve the problem Tullock identified. I survey the historical development of the term sycophancy within ancient Greek law as a revealing case study. Though a relatively innocuous pejorative in contemporary parlance, the term’s etymological roots stem from a formative process of ancient legal and institutional change within Athenian Greece. In the wake of specific legal reforms that expanded the scope of governmental authority under Solon (born 638–558 BCE), citizens were given explicit financial incentive to report violators of newly implemented public laws. Thereafter, social stigma surrounding third party legal representation leveraged the term sycophancy in reference to prosecutors motivated by private interests over the public welfare. Forgone social status and eventually formal criminal sanction emerged as offsetting differentials against the incentives of sycophancy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See: Zywicki (2008), Zywicki and Stringham (2013), Voigt (2017).

  2. Zywicki (2008) argues that Tullock’s claims against adversarialism are stronger than his case against common law rule making. Luppi and Parisi (2012) comparatively model rule making across the American and English systems finding confirmatory implications from Tullock’s secondary implications.

  3. Tullock (2005, p. 413) himself caveats and reserves much of his critique to the Anglo American common law system, especially within the latter twentieth century. He concedes a greater efficiency for the contemporary British system, as it possesses a “loser-pays” norm.

  4. See also (Harvey 1990, p. 105 fn 5).

  5. Harvey (1990, pp. 107–110) provides a thorough listing of the term’s pejorative uses throughout the classical canon.

  6. Barnett (1977) and Benson (1996) have noted similarly for other primitive and customary legal contexts that leveraged restitution over retributive punishments.

  7. Lofberg (1917, pp. 2–3) recreates the longer dialogue between Chremylus and the Sycophant, partially printed as the epigraph of this essay, as descriptive of the tension surrounding public v. private interest motivations in the legal process.

  8. Perhaps the most iconic source material description of primitive Greek legal processes is Homer’s description of Achilles shield in the Iliad, “…And in the middle law two talents of gold, to give to the one who delivered judgment most rightly among them (18.508).” Homer additionally describes the usage of impartial third parties elsewhere (Iliad 23. 485–487). Hesiod’s Theogony (81–90) reports similarly noting that good judges implement fair and welcomed rulings while de-escalating violence and conflict.

  9. MacDowell (1978, pp. 10–12) argues the bulk of legal references throughout the epics concern proprietary disputes. Similarly, Austin and Vidal-Naquet (1972, p. 25) argue the bulk of political and institutional change in ancient Greece centered on land disputes. See also: Calhoun (1927) and Cohen (1995).

  10. As wealthier citizens made payments to satisfy punitive sentences, poor Athenians were more often subjected to bondage. Thus, as formal state authority subsumed the right of bondage but retained the social norms of restitution, systemic inequality of bonded populations drew the public’s ire (see Allen 2000).

  11. The unique Athenian law of hubris is a similar example. In short, hubris was a charge pressed against an original plaintiff who lacked sufficient evidence or good cause to have originally pressed charges. It was a direct reference to the financial costs of time supposedly wasted by the initial defendant (Fisher 1990).

  12. Socrates trial (approximately 399 BCE) described in Plato’s Apology (37b-c) represents markedly different legal and punitive processes from earlier periods.

  13. See Everson (1984, p. 216) and (Perrin 1967, pp. 451–455).

  14. Osborne (1990, p. 92) notes the apparently systemic difference between sycophancy accusations in cases related to public relative to private violations. The latter having a rare occasion for the term, yet the former near universal invocation.

  15. Osborne (1990, p. 86) quotes Isocrates XXI.5 “[t]hose who are clever at speaking but poor’ are particularly keen to bring sycophantic allegations, and their favoured victims are those who are incapable as orators but able to pay out cash.”

  16. This sense of hostility against the rich has been challenged. See: Jones (1958, p. 36).

  17. Some have inferred sycophancy so prominent as to represent an entire professional class of citizens (Osborne 1990). While this specific claim is contested, the likely prominence of sycophantic behaviors and accusations throughout trial procedures is well empirically established and widely accepted (Harvey 1990, pp. 107–109).

  18. Harvey (1990, p. 106) cites “Lipsius 1905–1915, 449, Bonner and Smith (1938, pp. 56–57), MacDowell (1978, p. 64) and Harrison (1971, p. 83)” all documenting the formally criminal connotations of sycophancy.

  19. Other researchers have also made explicit comparisons between Ancient Greece and the common law tradition. See: Todd and Millet (1990) and Acemoglu and Robinson (2016).

References

  • Acemoglu, D., & Robinson, J. (2016). Paths to inclusive political institutions. Working Paper.

  • Allen, D. (1997). Imprisonment in classical Athens. The Classical Quarterly, 41(1), 121–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, D. (2000). The world of Prometheus, the politics of punishing in democratic Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T., & Hill, P. (2004). The not so wild, wild west: Property rights on the frontier. Palo Alto: Stanford Economics and Finance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1984). Everson, S. (ed.). The politics and the constitution of Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Austin, M., & Vidal-Naquet, P. (1972). Economic and social history of Ancient Greece, an introduction. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkan, I. (1936). Imprisonment as a penalty in Ancient Athens. Classical Philology, 31(4), 338–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, R. (1977). Restitution: A new paradigm for criminal justice. Ethics, 87, 279–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1968). Crime and punishment an economic approach. Journal of Political Economy, 76(2), 169–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benson, B. (1988). Legal evolution in primitive societies. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 144(5), 772–788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benson, B. (1989). The spontaneous evolution of commercial law. Southern Economic Journal, 55(3), 644–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benson, B. (1996). Restitution in theory and practice. Journal of Libertarian Studies, 11(1), 44–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, H. (1983). Law and revolution: The formation of the western legal tradition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Billheimer, A. (1938). The seisachtheia and inflation. The Classical Journal, 33(8), 471–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonner, R., & Smith, G. (1930–1938). The administration of justice from Homer to Aristotle, Vol. 2. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

  • Calhoun, G. (1927). The growth of criminal law in Ancient Greece. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartledge, P. (1990). Fowl play: A curious lawsuit in classical Athens. In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian law, politics and society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. (1995). Law, violence, and community in classical Athens. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. (2005). Introduction. In D. Cohen & M. Gagarin (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Ancient Greek law. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Amico, D. (2010). The prison in economics: Private and public incarceration in Ancient Greece. Public Choice, 145(3–4), 461–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damaska, M. (1986). The faces of justice and state authority: A comparative approach to the legal process. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demsetz, H. (1967). Towards a theory of property rights. The American Economic Review, 57(2), 347–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenberg, V. (1937). When did the polis rise? The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 57(2), 147–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellickson, R. (1994). Order without law: How neighbors settle disputes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everson, S. (Ed.). (1984). Aristotle: The politics and the constitution of Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finley, M. (1953). Economy and society in Ancient Greece. New York: The Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, N. (1990). The law of Hubris in Athens. In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian law, politics and society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, D. (1979). Private creation and enforcement of law: A historical case. Journal of Legal Studies, 8(2), 399–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gagarin, M. (2005). The unity of Greek law. In D. Cohen & M. Gagarin (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Ancient Greek law. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Greve, M. (2012). The upside-down constitution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, N. (1940). The seisachtheia and the nomothesia of Solon. The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 60, 71–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, N. (1961). Land tenure in Attica and Solon’s seisachtheia. The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 81, 76–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harding, P. (1974). Androtion’s view of Solon’s ‘seisachtheia’. Pheonix, 28(3), 282–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harper, D. (ed.) (2017). Sycophant. Online Etymology Dictionary. Accessed July 17, 2017. http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=sycophant&allowed_in_frame=0.

  • Harrison, A. (1971). The law of Athens. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, D. (1990). The sycophant and sycophancy: Vexatious redefinition? In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian Law, Politics and Society (pp. 103–122). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesiod (1991). The works and days, Theogony, and the shield of Herakles (trans: Lattimore, R.). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

  • Homer (1951). The Iliad of Homer (trans: Lattimore, R.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Hunter, V. (1994). Policing Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, A. (1958). Athenian democracy. New York: Frederick A. Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Porta, R., Lopez-de-Silanes, F., & Shleifer, A. (2008). The economic consequences of legal origins. Journal of Economic Literature, 46, 285–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, W., & Posner, R. (1987). The economic structure of tort law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsius (1905–1915) Das attische Recht und Rechtsverfahren, 3 vols in 4. I. Gerichtsverfassung; II.1. Offentliche Klagen; II.2 Privatlagen; III. Prozessgang. Leipzig (repr. Darmstadt 1966, Hildesheim 1984).

  • Lloyd, W. (1890). Seisachtheia. The Classical Review, 4(6), 271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lofberg, J. (1917). Sycophancy in Athens: A dissertation. Chicago: University of Chicago Libraries.

    Google Scholar 

  • Long, R. (1996). The Athenian constitution: Government by jury and referendum. Formulations. Available at: www.libertariannation.org.

  • Luppi, B., & Parisi, F. (2012). Litigation and legal evolution: Does procedure matter? Public Choice, 152(1/2), 181–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacDowell, D. (1978). The law in classical Athens. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maitland, F., & Pollock, F. (1895 [1965]). The history of English law before the time of Edward I. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Merriam-Webster’s Dictionary. (2017). Sycophant. Accessed Jul 17, 2017. https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/sycophant.

  • Merryman, J. (1969). The civil law tradition: An introduction to the legal systems of Europe and Latin America (3rd ed.). Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1992). Economics, organization and management. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, R. (1990). Vexatious litigation in classical Athens: Sycophancy and the sycophant. In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian law, politics and society (pp. 83–102). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Page, T. E. (Ed.). (1930). Aristophanes (Vol. I). London: William Heinemann Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Page, T. E. (Ed.). (1947). Aristophanes (Vol. III). London: William Heinemann Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parisi, F. (1995). Toward a theory of spontaneous law. Constitutional Political Economy, 6(3), 211–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pistor, K. (2006). Legal ground rules in coordinated and liberal market economies. In K. Hopt, E. Wymeersch, H. Kanda, & H. Baum (Eds.), Corporate governance in context: Corporations, states, and markets in Europe, Japan, and the US (pp. 249–280). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato’s apology (1997). J. Cooper (Ed.). Plato, complete works. Indianapolis: Hacket.

  • Posner, R. (1973). Economic analysis of law. Chicago: Wolters Kluwer Law & Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. (1980). A theory of primitive society, with special reference to primitive law. Journal of Law and Economics, 23(1), 1–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. (1981). The economics of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. (1994). What do judges maximize? (the same thing everybody else does). Supreme Court Economic Review, 3, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sah, R., & Stiglitz, J. (1986). The architecture of economic systems: Hierarchies and polyarchies. The American Economic Review, 76(4), 716–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, T. (1990). Plato and the Athenian law of theft. In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian law, politics and society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellin, T., & Wolfgang, M. (1964). The measurement of delinquency. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stringham, E. (2015). Private governance: Creating order in economic and social life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, S., & Millet, P. (1990). Law, society and Athens. In P. Cartledge, P. Millett, & S. Todd (Eds.), NOMOS: Essays in Athenian law, politics and society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal, 5(3), 224–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (2005). The case against the common law. In G. Rowley (Ed.), The selected works of Gordon Tullock (Vol. 9, pp. 399–455). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanderpool, E. (1980). The state prison of Athens. In K. De Vries (Ed.), From Athens to Gordion: The papers of a memorial symposium for Rodney S Young (pp. 17–31). Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voigt, S. (2017). Tullock on the common law: A loose-cannon iconoclast in action? Constitutional Political Economy, 28(1), 35–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. (1981). The economics of organization: The transaction cost approach. The American Journal of Sociology, 87(3), 548–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yandle, B. (1983). Bootleggers and Baptists: The education of a regulatory economist. Regulation, 7(3), 12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zywicki, T. (2008). Spontaneous order and the common law: Gordon Tullock’s critique. Public Choice, 135(1/2), 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zywicki, T., & Stringham, E. (2013). Common law and economic efficiency. In F. Parisi (Ed.), The Production of Legal Rules (pp. 107–131). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel J. D’Amico.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

D’Amico, D.J. The law and economics of sycophancy. Const Polit Econ 29, 424–439 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-018-9261-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-018-9261-6

Keywords

Navigation