Skip to main content
Log in

Strategic and expressive voting

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Critics of the expressive account of voting have argued that it is inconsistent with strategic voting. Since there is strong evidence that people vote strategically, this has been taken to show that many voters are at least partially instrumentally motivated. This paper argues that strategic voting in the relevant sense is consistent with entirely expressive political motivation. Building on an earlier suggestion by Geoffrey Brennan, I model voters as expressively valuing ideological position as well as the strategic pursuit of expressively-defined preferences. This model predicts strategic voting without instrumental preferences entering the voter’s calculus at all. I also suggest that expressive preferences for strategic behaviour can be usefully analysed in terms of dispositional choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For other objections, see Edlin et al. (2007), Mackie (2012).

  2. Expressive voting and dispositional politics are two central aspects of the emerging “revisionist public choice theory” being spearheaded by Brennan and Hamlin (2008). There are already important connections between these ideas (Hamlin 2006, pp. 9–10), and in this paper I build on these connections.

  3. Another way of thinking about C P would be as a transformation of k, with the transformation being motivated by an expressive preference for thinking of oneself as politically efficacious. If k is small but positive, the voter may recognize that their vote has virtually zero chance of being decisive but when making expressive choices treat the probability as much higher. I prefer the first interpretation of C P as a mathematically distinct variable, since the common idea that voters are contributing to a collective decision even though they know none will be decisive does not intuitively seem like an exaggerated probability. Yet another possibility would be to replace C P with k but insist that voters only care about which option has the highest expected value (i.e. which is the best choice) and do not discount the strategic superiority of the choice by the insignificance of the individual. On this interpretation, people see politics as a game and want to make the optimal moves. I find this intuitively appealing but I will stick with C P for reasons of analytic clarity and simplicity.

  4. Individuals likely receive psychic payoffs from having their preferred political party win, but voting in order to increase the probability of these payoffs would be instrumental rather than expressive.

  5. It should also be noted that closeness may increase the salience of the election and thus increase the unsophisticated expressive value of voting.

  6. Note, however, that votes wasted in a short term and strictly electoral sense might be valuable if victory margins affect government behaviour via a mandate effect or influence a party’s prospects in future elections (Stigler 1972; Fowler and Smirnov 2007; Mackie 2010).

  7. If we consider political dispositions as influencing not simply voting choices but a range of political activity from conversations at the pub to the signing of petitions to the wearing of campaign badges, a strategic disposition appears more attractive. Individuals have many avenues for expressing their ideological preferences—their expressively ideal point—and if standard economic logic applies here the existence of such substitutes for sincere ideological voting will decrease the quantity demanded. In the dispositional terms above, the existence of other outlets would decrease the value of β. Strategic voters could express idealism in the pub by proclaiming the rightness of the extreme view while expressing seriousness and practicality in the voting booth by voting for the lesser of two evils, and this might be expected to create higher aggregate expressive payoff.

References

  • Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics, 1236–1239.

  • Blais, A. (2006). What affects voter turnout? Annual Review of Political Science, 9, 111–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G. (2001). Five rational actor accounts of the welfare state. Kyklos, 54(2–3), 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G. (2008). Psychological dimensions in voter choice. Public Choice, 137(3–4), 475–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (1995). Economizing on virtue. Constitutional Political Economy, 6(1), 35–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (1998). Expressive voting and electoral equilibrium. Public Choice, 95(1), 149–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (2000). Democratic devices and desires. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (2008). Revisionist public choice theory. New Political Economy, 13(1), 77–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. E. (1984). Inefficient unanimity. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 1(1), 151–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. E. (1985). The impartial spectator goes to Washington: Toward a Smithian theory of electoral behavior. Economics and Philosophy, 1(2), 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. E. (1989). Large numbers, small costs: The uneasy foundation of democratic rule. In G. Brennan & L. E. Lomasky (Eds.), Politics and process: New essays in democratic thought (pp. 42–59). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. E. (1993). Democracy and decision: The pure theory of electoral preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1984). Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications. In J. M. Buchanan & R. D. Tollison (Eds.), The theory of public choice II (pp. 11–22). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2002). Systematically biased beliefs about economics: Robust evidence of judgemental anomalies from the survey of Americans and economists on the economy. Economic Journal, 112(479), 433–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. R., & Guerette, S. D. (1992). An experimental study of expressive voting. Public Choice, 73(3), 251–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (2004). Is normative rational choice theory self-defeating? Ethics, 115(1), 122–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T., & Hanson, R. (2004). Are disagreements honest? Unpublished manuscript, George Mason University.

  • Cox, G. W. (1997). Making votes count: Strategic coordination in the world’s electoral systems. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowding, K. (2005). Is it rational to vote? Five types of answer and a suggestion. The British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 7(3), 442–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edlin, A., Gelman, A., & Kaplan, N. (2007). Voting as a rational choice why and how people vote to improve the well-being of others. Rationality and Society, 19(3), 293–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T., Gailmard, S., & Sandroni, A. (2009). Moral bias in large elections: Theory and experimental evidence. American Political Science Review, 103(02), 175–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, A. J. (1996). A further experimental study of expressive voting. Public Choice, 88(1), 171–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, J. H., & Smirnov, O. (2007). Mandates, parties, and voters: How elections shape the future. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glazer, A. (2008). Voting to anger and to please others. Public Choice, 134(3), 247–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E., & Roberts, K. W. (1975). The ethical voter. The American Political Science Review, 69(3), 926–928.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, A. (2006). Political dispositions and dispositional politics. In G. Eusepi & A. Hamlin (Eds.), Beyond conventional economics: The limits of rational behaviour in political decision making (pp. 3–16). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, A., & Jennings, C. (2011). Expressive political behaviour: Foundations, scope and implications. British Journal of Political Science, 41(3), 645–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, R. (2006). Uncommon priors require origin disputes. Theory and Decision, 61(4), 319–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillman, A. (2010). Expressive behavior in economics and politics. European Journal of Political Economy, 26(4), 403–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iyengar, S., & Hahn, K. S. (2009). Red media, blue media: Evidence of ideological selectivity in media use. Journal of Communication, 59(1), 19–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iyengar, S., Norpoth, H., & Hahn, K. S. (2004). Consumer demand for election news: The horserace sells. Journal of Politics, 66(1), 157–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamenica, E., & Egan Brad, L. (2014). Voters, dictators, and peons: Expressive voting and pivotality. Public Choice, 159(1–2), 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (2010). Why it’s rational to vote. Unpublished manuscript, San Diego: University of California.

  • Mackie, G. (2011). An examination of the expressive theory of voting. Unpublished manuscript, San Diego: University of California.

  • Mackie, G. (2012). Rational ignorance and beyond. In H. Landemore & J. Elster (Eds.), Collective wisdom: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 290–318). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: WH Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuessler, A. A. (2000). A logic of expressive choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shayo, M., & Harel, A. (2012). Non-consequentialist voting. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 81(1), 299–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, R. S., & Wagner, G. A. (2004). Expressive voting and government redistribution: Testing Tullock’s ‘charity of the uncharitable’. Public Choice, 119(1), 143–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J. (1972). Economic competition and political competition. Public Choice, 13(1), 91–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2006). Motivated skepticism in the evaluation of political beliefs. American Journal of Political Science, 50(3), 755–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taber, C. S., Lodge, M., & Glathar, J. (2001). The motivated construction of political judgments. In J. H. Kuklinski (Ed.), Citizens and politics: Perspectives from political psychology (pp. 198–226). London: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). Toward a mathematics of politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1971). The charity of the uncharitable. Western Economic Journal, 9(4), 379–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyran, J. R. (2004). Voting when money and morals conflict: An experimental test of expressive voting. Journal of Public Economics, 88(7), 1645–1664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Geoff Brennan, Keith Dowding, the editors, and two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brad R. Taylor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Taylor, B.R. Strategic and expressive voting. Const Polit Econ 26, 159–170 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-014-9180-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-014-9180-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation