Skip to main content
Log in

Amorphic kinds: Cluster’s last stand?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I raise a puzzle case for “cluster” accounts of natural kinds—the homeostatic property cluster and stable property cluster accounts, especially—on the basis of their expected treatment of the metaphysics of certain disease kinds. Some kinds, I argue, fail to exhibit the co-instantiated property clusters these cluster views take to be (partly) constitutive of natural kinds. Some genetic diseases, for example, have archetypical instances with few or none of the pathological processes or symptoms associated with the kind: their instances are typified by a single dispositional property. I dub such kinds ‘amorphic’, owing to their limited morphology, and try out a number of ways in which these kinds might be treated in terms of property clusters, adapting responses cluster theorists have offered to the problem of polymorphic species. Finding these responses wanting, I conclude that cluster accounts are unlikely to be the best account of the metaphysics of amorphic kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. What I am calling the HPC “family” includes (at least): Boyd (1991, 1999), Kornblith (1993), Griffiths (1999), Magnus (2011), Williams (2011), Wilson et al. (2007), Slater (2015), Chakravartty (2007) and Martínez (2015).

  2. This is actually a case of sexual dimorphism, but it is at the heart of the puzzle case. Species that change dramatically over their lifetimes—such as butterflies—offer further examples, as do polyphenic species, like ants and bees.

  3. Wilson et al. (2007) discuss the many deaths that biology rained down on essentialism.

  4. I say modified because [E] makes reference to the clusters in [C], and so, without modification, not satisfying [C] entails not satisfying [E].

  5. Herein we find additional drivers of the are/consist wedge: if one insists that [C] is part of what kinds are, and not just in what they consist, it follows that if PKU is not a cluster kind, then it’s not a natural kind either.

  6. No event can be the cause of itself. Hence, if the symptoms are part of the disease, then it cannot be the disease that causes them. An early part of a process can explain a later part, but treating the symptoms as part of the disease would rule out this sort of splitting.

  7. Some diseases are dispositional states, but not all. In fact, I deny that there is a single ontological category to which diseases belong.

  8. A recent study by Murphy et al. (2008) suggests that the UK has far fewer incidents of untreated PKU than sheer frequency of the disease predicts. The disease impacts roughly 1 in 10,000 people, but it is thought that only 150 current cases have advanced without treatment. Most US states make screening for PKU a standard part of newborn testing, leading to similarly low numbers of advanced cases.

  9. That amorphic kinds are identified by a single property means that the roles these kinds play in their respective sciences cannot be quite the same as that of the cluster kinds, but that should not force us into an ad hoc conclusion regarding the possibility of single-property clusters. I briefly revisit this matter in the conclusion.

  10. What I am proposing is a minimalist form of essentialism, suited—if it is—to answering the consist question regarding amorphic kinds. It therefore does not carry with it all of the potentially negative aspects we associate with the (traditional) essentialism of Aristotle, Kripke, or Putnam. To wit, the present essentialism does not require kinds to fall into a single, unified, hierarchical, monistic system.

References

  • Aristotle (1975) Categories. (Trans.: Ackrill JL). Oxford University Press

  • Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61:127–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson R (ed) Species—new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty A (2007) A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper R (2005) Classifying madness. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper R (2007) Psychiatry and the philosophy of science. McGill-Queen’s Press, Kingston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dragulinescu S (2010) Diseases as natural kinds. Theor Med Bioeth 31:347–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M, Matthen M (2005) Taxonomy, polymorphism, and history: an introduction to population structure theory. Philos Sci 72:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson R (ed) Species—new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith H (1993) Inductive inference and its natural ground. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1980) Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2007) The end of diseases. Philos Top 35:265–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus PD (2011) Drakes, seadevils, and similarity fetishism. Biol Philos 26:857–870

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus PD (2014) NK ≠ HPC. Philos Q 64:471–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martínez M (2015) Informationally-connected property clusters and polymorphism. Biol Philos 30:99–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1884) A system of logic. Longmans, Harlow

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy G et al (2008) Adults with untreated phenylketonuria: out of sight, out of mind. Br J Psychiatry 193(6):501–502

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1975) Mind, language and reality. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reznek L (1987) The nature of disease. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels R, Ferreira M (2010) Why don’t concepts constitute a natural kind? Behav Brain Sci 33:222–223

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2013) Are species real? An essay on the metaphysics of species. Palgrave-MacMillian, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2015) Natural kindness. B J Philos Sci 66:375–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitbeck C (1977) Causation in medicine: the disease entity model. Philos Sci 44:619–637

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams NE (2007) The factory model of disease. Monist 90:555–584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams NE (2011) Arthritis and nature’s joints. In: Campbell JK et al (eds) Carving nature at its joints—topics in contemporary philosophy, vol 8. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 199–230

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R et al (2007) When traditional essentialism fails: biological natural kinds. Philos Top 35:189–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to all those who helped improve this paper: the audience in Madrid; the journal referees; D Limbaugh; and J Beverley.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil E. Williams.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Williams, N.E. Amorphic kinds: Cluster’s last stand?. Biol Philos 33, 14 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9625-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9625-3

Keywords

Navigation