Skip to main content
Log in

The Brentano School and the History of Analytic Philosophy: Reply to Röck

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In ‘Brentano’s Methodology as a Path through the Divide’, Röck makes two related claims. (A) Röck argues that there exists a philosophical dilemma between description and logical analysis, and that the current divide between continental phenomenology and analytic philosophy may be seen as a consequence of the dilemma. (B) Röck further argues that Brentano’s work integrates description and logical analysis in a way which ‘can provide a suitable starting point for an equally successful integration of these methods in contemporary philosophy’ (Axiomathes 27:475–489, 2017). Without disputing Röck’s claim (B) about the suitability of Brentano’s work for such an integration, this paper questions (A) by examining the influence of Brentano and his school on early analytic philosophy. As recent scholarship in the history of analytic philosophy demonstrates, contrary to Röck’s contention, many prominent analytic philosophers conversed with Brentano and his school’s conceptions of phenomenological description.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Under the banner of ‘early analytic philosophy’ I speak of those works and figures that are commonly acknowledged as canonical in the analytic tradition, though placing them under the banner ‘analytic philosophy’ would be, strictly speaking, an anachronism. The term only first occurs during the 1930 s (Beaney 2013, 44), though major figures and works already existed decades earlier. I do not mean to imply that early analytic philosophers, from Frege to the Vienna Circle, were somehow less ‘analytic’ than those that come later.

  2. It is clear that Röck’s thesis is not identical to Dummett’s, since she at times she speaks more broadly about Brentano’s influence on analytic philosophy through his work ‘on the refinement and clarification of language, of concepts, and arguments, and on the improvement of the logical structures on which the arguments are based’ (p. 482). Nonetheless, Röck also makes the claim that Brentano’s analytic reception is filtered through Frege’s semantic focus.

  3. On connected family resemblance accounts of analytic and continental philosophy (see e.g. Stroll 2000; Glock 2008; Reynolds and Chase 2011).

  4. It is also questionable whether Frege himself undertook the linguistic turn (see e.g. Baker and Hacker 1983; Glock 2008, p. 131).

  5. For further discussion of Moore’s influence by the Brentano school, (see Milkov 2004).

  6. Citing the same passage, Poli, goes as far as to call Brentano ‘one of the founders of the analytic movement and in particular of the Vienna Circle’ (2017, p. 5; see also Albertazzi 1996, 5). Interpreted literally this is true insofar as Brentano’s chair at the University of Vienna passed from Mach to Boltzman to Schlick (and later Carnap) (Poli 1997, pp. 19–20).

  7. See Haddock (2008, p. 5); Stone 2010; Carus 2016. Contrary to Haddock (2008), Stone (2010) argues that the waning of Husserl’s influence on Carnap already began in Der Raum. Contrary to both, Carus (2016) argues that this change of outlook only occurred after 1924.

  8. One such interesting case is that of Kurt Gödel, who at one time had been a member of the Circle, would later develop an interest in Husserl’s work (see Føllesdal 1995).

  9. Neumann wrote literary works, and did not publish any works in academic philosophy.

  10. Regardless of whether it is called ‘phenomenology’ or not, description took center-stage in Wittgenstein’s work. He went so far as to claim that ‘Philosophy really is “purely descriptive”’ (Wittgenstein 1958, p. 18).

  11. (See e.g. Mulligan 2003, pp. 264–266). Mulligan points to a number of convergences between the Brentano school and Oxford philosophers including Urmson, Grice, Kneale, Dummett, Gareth Evans, Bernard Williams, Kit Fine, and Timothy Williamson; some of these similarities relate to Brentano’s descriptive project.

  12. The following interesting pattern emerges from the history of Brentano’s analytic reception outlined above: a number of analytic philosophers, with Carnap and Ryle being the most prominent examples, acknowledge having been deeply influenced by Brentano’s school in the early part of their careers, while proceeding to disavow this influence in later work. Scholars have questioned such disavowals (e.g. Haddock 2008; Thomasson 2002), which played a significant role in creating the idea that there exists a divide between analytic philosophy and phenomenology (see Vrahimis 2013). Carnap, Ryle, and others listed above, would continue their engagement with both descriptive and analytic projects, even after having presented the Brentanian influence on both aspects of their work as waning.

References

  • Albertazzi L (1996) A cubist state of mind: Meinong’s ontology. Axiomathes 7(1–2):5–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1970) A plea for excuses. In: Philosophical papers. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Baker GP, Hacker PMS (1983) Frege: logical excavations. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaney M (2013) The historiography of analytic philosophy. In: Beaney M (ed) The Oxford handbook of the history of analytic philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bell D (1999) A very British coup? In: O Hear A (ed) German Philosophy since Kant. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1973) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (trans: Rancurello AC, Terrell DB, and McAlister L). Routledge London

  • Carnap R (1921–1926) Ms. “Vom Chaos zur Wirklichkeit” (mit Notizen zum Konstitution-System), http://digital.library.pitt.edu/islandora/object/pitt%3A31735061814202

  • Carnap R (1922) Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wissenschaftlehre. Kant-studien 56:63–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1928). Der Logische Aufbau Der Welt. Leipzig, Meiner. Translated as: Carnap R (1967) The Logical Structure of the World. Pseudoproblems in Philosophy (trans: George R A). University of California Press, Berkeley

  • Carus AW (2016) Carnap and phenomenology: What happened in 1924? In: Damböck C (ed) Influences on the Aufbau. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm R (1957) Perceiving: A philosophical study. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm R (1986) Brentano and intrinsic value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1993) Origins of analytical philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Føllesdal D (1995) Gödel and Husserl. In: Hintikka J (ed) From Dedekind to Gödel. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (2000) A parting of the ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Open Court, Chigago

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock HJ (2008) What is analytic philosophy?. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin N, Jacquette D (2009) Introduction. In: Griffin N, Jacquette D (eds) Russell vs. Meinong: The Legacy of “On Denoting”. Oxon: Routledge

  • Haddock GER (2008) The Young Carnap’s unknown Master: Husserl’s influence on Der Raum and Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Ashgate, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill CO (2017) Introduction to Paul Linke’s ‘Gottlob Frege as Philosopher’. In: Poli R (ed) The Brentano Puzzle. Routledge, Oxon

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer W (2003) Logical empiricism and phenomenology: Felix Kaufmann. In: Stadler F (ed) The Vienna Circle and logical empiricism: re-evaluation and future perspectives. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette D (2009) Review of The Young Carnap’s Unknown Master: Husserl’s Influence on Der Raum and Der Logische Aufbau Der Welt. Hist Philos Logic 30(2):194–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann F (1940) Phenomenology and logical empiricism. In: Farber M (ed) Philosophical essays in memory of Edmund Husserl. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann F (1941) Strata of experience. Philos Phenomenol Res 1(3):313–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linke P (2017) Gottlob Frege as philosopher. In: Poli R (ed) The Brentano puzzle. Routledge, Oxon

    Google Scholar 

  • McAlister LL (1974) Chisholm and Brentano on intentionality. Rev Metaphys 28(2):328–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Milkov N (2004) G. E. Moore and the Greifswald objectivists on the given and the beginning of analytic philosophy. Axiomathes 14(4):361–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milkov N (2017) Russell and Husserl (1905–1918): the Not-So-Odd couple. In: Stone P (ed) Bertrand Russell’s life and legacy. Vernon Press, Wilmington

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk R (1996) Was Russell an analytical philosopher? Ratio 9(3):227–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monk R (2014) The temptations of phenomenology: Wittgenstein, the synthetic a priori and the “Analytic a Posteriori”’. Int J Philos Stud 22(3):312–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1903) Review of the origin of the knowledge of right and wrong. By Franz Brentano. Int J Ethics 14(1):115–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan K (2003) Searle, Derrida and the ends of phenomenology. In: Smith B (ed) The Cambridge companion to Searle. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nasim OW (2008) Bertrand Russell and the Edwardian philosophers: constructing the world. Palgrave Macmillan, Hampshire

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson ES (2018) Dilthey and Carnap: the feeling of life, the scientific worldview, and the elimination of metaphysics. In: Feichtinger J, Fillafer FL, Surman J (eds) The worlds of positivism: a global intellectual history. Palgrave Macmillan, Hampshire, pp 1770–1930

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver A (1999) A few more remarks on logical form. Proc Aristot Soc 99:247–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard S (2010) Royaumont revisited. Br J Hist Philos 18(5):899–924

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poli R (1997) In itinere: pictures from Central European philosophy. In: Poli R (ed) In Itinere: European cities and the birth of modern scientific philosophy. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli R (2017) The Brentano puzzle: an introduction. In: Poli R (ed) The Brentano puzzle. Routledge, Oxon

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds J, Chase J (2011) Analytic versus Continental: arguments on the methods and value of philosophy. Stocksfield, Acumen

    Google Scholar 

  • Röck T (2017) Brentano’s methodology as a path through the divide: on combining phenomenological descriptions and logical analysis. Axiomathes 27:475–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1905) On denoting. Mind 14(56):479–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B (2004) Philosophy in the twentieth century. In: Sceptical Essays. New York, Routledge

  • Ryle G (1927) Review of Essentiale Fragen Ein Beitrag zum Problem des Wesens, by Roman Ingarden. Mind 36(143):366–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle G (1929) Review of Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit. Mind 38(151):355–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle G (1970) Autobiographical. In: Wood OP, Pitcher G (eds) Ryle: a collection of critical essays. Anchor Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle G (1971) Phenomenology vs. The Concept of Mind. In: Collected Papers: Critical essays (Vol. 1). London, Hutchinson

  • Ryle G (1973) Intentionality-theory and the nature of thinking. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 2(104/105):255–265

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle G, Hodges HA, Acton HB (1932) Symposium: phenomenology. Proc Aristot Soc Suppl Vol 11:68–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanford D (1997) Chisholm on Brentano’s Thesis. In: Hahn LE (ed) The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm (The Library of Living Philosophers: Volume 25). Chicago, La Salle, Open Court

  • Smith JF (1985) The Russell-Meinong debate. Res 45(3):305–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B (1994) Austrian philosophy: the legacy of Franz Brentano. Open Court Publishing Company, Chicago

  • Stone AD (2010) On the sources and implications of Carnap’s Der Raum. Stud Hist Philos Sci 41:65–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroll A (2000) Twentieth-century analytic philosophy. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C, Ayer AJ (1959) Symposium: phenomenology and linguistic analysis. Proc Aristotel Soc Suppl Vol 33:93–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2002) Phenomenology and the development of analytic philosophy. South J Philos 40(1):115–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2007) Conceptual analysis in phenomenology and ordinary language philosophy. In: Beaney M (ed) The analytic turn: analysis in early analytic philosophy and phenomenology. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat E (1972) Description as the method of philosophy: a reply to Mr Pettit. In: Mays W, Brown SC (eds) Linguistic analysis and phenomenology. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrahimis A (2013) Encounters between analytic and continental philosophy. Hampshire, Palgrave-Macmillan

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vrahimis A (2014) Wittgenstein and the phenomenological movement: reply to Monk. Int J Philos Stud 22(3):341–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vrahimis A (2018) Is there a methodological divide between analytic and continental philosophy of music?: reply to Roholt. J Aesthet Art Crit 76(1):108–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1958) Preliminary studies for the “philosophical investigations” generally known as the blue and brown books. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1978) On Heidegger on being and dread. In: Murray M (ed) Heidegger and modern philosophy. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L, Waismann F, Baker GP (2003) The voices of Wittgenstein. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Vrahimis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vrahimis, A. The Brentano School and the History of Analytic Philosophy: Reply to Röck. Axiomathes 28, 363–374 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-018-9374-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-018-9374-6

Keywords

Navigation