Skip to main content
Log in

From Biological Determination to Entangled Causation

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Biologists and philosophers often use the language of determination in order to describe the nature of developmental phenomena. Accounts in terms of determination have often been reductionist. One common idea is that DNA is supposed to play a special explanatory role in developmental explanations, namely, that DNA is a developmental determinant. In this article we try to make sense of determination claims in developmental biology. Adopting a manipulationist approach, we shall first argue that the notion of developmental determinant is causal. We suggest that two different theses concerning developmental determination can be articulated: determination of occurrence and structural determination. We shall argue that, while the first thesis is problematic, the second, opportunely qualified, is feasible. Finally, we shall argue that an analysis of biological causation in terms of determination cannot account for entangled dynamics. Characterising causal entanglement as a particular kind of interactive causation whereby difference-making causes ascribable to different levels of biological organisation influence a particular ontogenetic outcome, we shall, via two illustrative examples, diagnose some potential limits of a reductionist, molecular and intra-level understanding of biological causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We prefer the expression “phenotypic outcome” to “gene product” because the latter betrays a DNA-centric causal bias.

  2. Here the point is simply that synchronic constitutive analysis accounts for the difference in spatial organisation of the two biosystems independently of the nature of the relationship between its constituent entities. This is sufficient to vindicate a principled constitution-causality distinction. At the same time, the direction of the arrow implies causation and a relationship of diachronic ‘influencing’ between the entities. It is for this reason that constitutive analysis is intrinsically limited when dealing with biological processes.

  3. Halder et al.’s (1995) genetic experiments with Drosophila in which the expression of gene Ey is argued to be “necessary and sufficient to induce ectopic eyes” (Halder et al. 1995, p. 1791) even in wings and antennae seems to contravene our argument. However, note that the claim that Ey determines eye morphogenesis should be qualified. First of all, this gene is not the only one regulating this morphogenetic process because “…we estimate that more than 2500 genes are involved in eye morphogenesis” (Halder et al. 1995, p. 1791). Nonetheless, some interesting determination claims remain compatible with the evidence, namely that either Ey causes one or a series of switch points or even that the entire developmental trajectory is entirely regulated by genomic resources (i.e., that all its switch-points are caused by genomic inputs, e.g. Ey and thousands of other genes). This latter hypothesis is a form of genetic determinism because an adult phenotype would be fully determined by genomic inputs. At the end of this section we show that even such hypotheses are suspicious.

  4. This applies to the Ey case as well (see note 3). Gene expression processes do not happen in a vacuum but in a developmental context that is rich in extra-genomic developmental resources such as molecular agents and environmental inputs. To emphasise Ey’s and the 2.500 other genes’s causal contribution to the process of eye morphogenesis in Drosophila is to dismiss as causally irrelevant these extra-genomic resources of the developmental context.

  5. The concept of determination of occurrence seen in Sect. 4 (i.e., that a developmental factor is a necessary and sufficient condition for the occurrence of a specific developmental outcome at a specific switch point) and the concept of structural determination (i.e., that a developmental factor is a highly specific cause that fully accounts for the structural features of a developmental outcome) to be articulated in this section are different. The reason is that a difference-making cause could be a structural determinant without being an occurrence determinant.

  6. It should be added that these naturally produced molecular conformations should not be caused by DNA differences. For instance, they might be phenotypic mutations (Bürger et al. 2006).

  7. Evolutionary studies concerning the nature of extant bacterial polymerases might indeed substantiate this argument if natural “manipulations” were discovered. We thank Staffan Müller–Wille for this suggestion.

  8. It should be noted that Noble himself speaks explicitly of downward causation (2006).

  9. It should also be noted that Lesne and Victor (2006) indifferently use expressions like “emergent property”, “regulation” and “constraint”. Whether the notion of constraint used by Lesne and Victor bears a close relationship with that articulated by Umerez and Mossio (2013) is beyond the scope of the paper.

References

  • Baravalle L, Vecchi D (2016) Beyond blindness: on the role of organism and environment in trial generation. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C Stud Hist Philos Biolog Biomed Sci 60:25–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner M (2009) Interventionist causal exclusion and non-reductive physicalism. Int Stud Philos Sci 23(2):161–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (2015) Can mechanistic explanation be reconciled with scale-free constitution and dynamics? Stud Hist Philos Biolog Biomed Sci 2015(53):84–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bürger R et al (2006) Why are phenotypic mutation rates much higher than genotypic mutation rates? Genetics 172:197–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clancy S (2008) RNA transcription by RNA polymerase: prokaryotes vs eukaryotes. Nat Educ 1(1):125

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver C, Bechtel B (2006) Mechanism. In: Sarkar S, Pfeifer J (eds) The philosophy of science: an encyclopedia. Routledge, New York, pp 469–478

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Bechtel W (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 20:715–734

    Google Scholar 

  • Crews D (2003) Sex determination: where environment and genetics meet. Evolut Dev 5(1):50e55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick F (1958) On protein synthesis. Symp Soc Exp Biol 12:138–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis MC (2017) The essential activities of the bacterial sigma factor. Can J Microbiol 63:89–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delbrück M (1971) Aristotle-totle-totle. In: Monod J, Borek E (eds) Of microbes and life. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 50–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Dhouailly D (1983) Early events in retinoic acid-induced ptilopody in the chick embryo. Wilehm Roux Arch Dev Biol 192(1):21–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen MI (2013) No levels, no problems: downward causation in neuroscience. Philos Sci 80(5):1042–1052

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S (2000) Developmental biology. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S, Sarkar S (2000) Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century. Dev Dyn 219:1–9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P, Stotz K (2013) Genetics and philosophy: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P et al (2015) Measuring causal specificity. Philos Sci 82(4):529–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halder G, Callaerts P, Gehring WJ (1995) Induction of ectopic eyes by targeted expression of the eyeless gene in Drosophila. Science 267(5205):1788–1792

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartl FU et al (2011) Molecular chaperones in protein folding and proteostasis. Nature 475:324–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, p 65

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner M, Gerhart JC (2005) The plausibility of life. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler M, Wagner GP (2001) How molecular is molecular developmental biology? A reply to Alex Rosenberg’s reductionism redux: computing the embryo. Biol Philos 16:53–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lesne A (2013) Multiscale analysis of biological systems. Acta Biotheor 61(1):3–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lesne A, Victor JM (2006) Chromatin fiber functional organisation: some plausible models. Eur Phys J E 19:279–290

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin M (2012) Morphogenetic fields in embryogenesis, regeneration, and cancer: non-local control of complex patterning. BioSystems 109:243–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R, Levins R (2007) Biology under the influence: dialectical essays on the coevolution of nature and society. Monthly Review Press, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Maffini MV, Calabro JM, Soto AM, Sonnenschein C (2005) Stromal regulation of neoplastic development: age-dependent normalization of neoplastic mammary cells by mammary stroma. Am J Pathol 67:1405–1410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahner M, Bunge M (1997) Foundations of biophilosophy. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Malaterre C (2011) Making sense of downward causation in manipulationism. Hist Philos Life Sci 33:537–562

    Google Scholar 

  • Malyshev DA et al (2014) A semi-synthetic organism with an expanded genetic alphabet. Nature 509:385–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2006) The music of life biology beyond the genome. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2008) Genes and causation. Philos Trans R Soc A 366:3001–3015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2012) A theory of biological relativity: no privileged level of causation. Interface Focus 2(1):55–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D, Noble SJ (1984) A model of S.A. node electrical activity using a modification of the Di Francesco-Noble equations. Proc R Soc B 222:295–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noss RF (1990) Indicators for monitoring biodiversity: a hierarchical approach. Conserv Biol 4(4):1990

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pierce BA (2012) Genetics: a conceptual approach. W.H. Freeman & Co., New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Raatikainen P (2010) Causation, exclusion, and the special sciences. Erkenntnis 3:349–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (1997) Reductionism redux: computing the embryo. Biol Philos 12:445–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2005) Molecular models of life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L, Sober E (2007) Epiphenomenalism. The do’s and don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 235–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Umerez J, Mossio M (2013) Constraint. In: Dubitzky W, Wolkenhauer O, Yokota H, Cho K-H (eds) Encyclopedia of systems biology. Springer, New York, pp 490–493

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vecchi D, Hernandez I (2014) The epistemological resilience of the concept of morphogenetic field. In: Minelli A, Pradeu T (eds) Towards a theory of development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 79–94

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1939) Genes as evocators in development. Growth 1:S37–S44

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters K (2007) Causes that make a difference. J Philos 104(11):551–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2006) The central dogma as a thesis of causal specificity. Hist Philos Life Sci 28:595–610

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert L (1991) The triumph of the embryo. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2008) Mental causation and neural mechanisms. In: Hohwy J, Kallestrup J (eds) Being reduced: new essays on reductive explanation and special science causation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 218–262

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2010) Causation in biology: stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biol Philos 25:287–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski P (2014) Rethinking micro–macro relations. In: Zahle J, Collin F (eds) Rethinking the individualism-holism debate. Springer International Publishing, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuckerkandl E, Villet R (1988) Concentration-affinity equivalence in gene regulation: convergence of genetic and environmental effects. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 85:4784–4788

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

D.V. acknowledges the financial support of the Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (FCT Grant No. SFRH/BPD/99879/2014, BIODECON R&D Project. Grant PTDC/IVC-HFC/1817/2014) and of the Fondo Nacional de Desarrollo Científico y Tecnológico de Chile (Grant No. 1171017 FONDECYT REGULAR). We thank Lorenzo Baravalle, Maurizio Esposito, Gil Santos and the reviewers for feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Davide Vecchi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vecchi, D., Miquel, PA. & Hernández, I. From Biological Determination to Entangled Causation. Acta Biotheor 67, 19–46 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-018-9339-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-018-9339-6

Keywords

Navigation