Skip to main content
Log in

Natural Selection and Drift as Individual-Level Causes of Evolution

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I critically evaluate Reisman and Forber’s (Philos Sci 72(5):1113–1123, 2005) arguments that drift and natural selection are population-level causes of evolution based on what they call the manipulation condition. Although I agree that this condition is an important step for identifying causes for evolutionary change, it is insufficient. Following Woodward, I argue that the invariance of a relationship is another crucial parameter to take into consideration for causal explanations. Starting from Reisman and Forber’s example on drift and after having briefly presented the criterion of invariance, I show that once both the manipulation condition and the criterion of invariance are taken into account, drift, in this example, should better be understood as an individual-level rather than a population-level cause. Later, I concede that it is legitimate to interpret natural selection and drift as population-level causes when they rely on genuinely indeterministic events and some cases of frequency-dependent selection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In population genetics, the term ‘force’ is used more often than the term ‘cause.’ I consider them as roughly equivalent, although I will use the term ‘cause’ throughout the paper. This is because I will make use of concepts developed in the philosophical literature on causation. For more on the difference between the use of these two terms in evolutionary theory see Hitchcock and Velasco (2014).

  2. This division into four causes is to some extent arbitrary. Some authors would for example add sex or recombination as other forces or causes.

  3. See for example Bouchard and Rosenberg (2004), Matthen and Ariew (2002, 2009), Millstein (2006), Northcott (2010), Reisman and Forber (2005), Rosenberg and Bouchard (2005), Shapiro and Sober (2007), Stephens (2004), Walsh (2000, 2007, 2010), Walsh et al. (2002), Ariew et al. (2015), Walsh et al. (2017), and Otsuka (2016).

  4. To be sure, most causal explanations involve the use of statistics in evolutionary biology. The statisticalists have no objection to that, but they claim that referring to causes is in principle dispensable for evolutionary explanations.

  5. Otsuka et al. (2011, see also Northcott 2010), argue that context independence is far from being a necessary condition for a relationship to be considered as causal. Context dependence is in fact a feature of causal modeling.

  6. In this paper, “individual” should be understood here as “any entity below the level of the population.” As pointed out by Charles Pence (personal communication), this notion of “individual” might refer to something different from what the individual causalists mean by this term, since for them “individuals” often refer to “individual organisms.” If that is the case, I accept this departure from that of the individual causalists.

  7. Stephens’ (2004) position seems close to that of Reisman and Forber. He assumes that drift and NS are population-level causes: “the point is that the effect of drift is only properly understood at the population level. It is a population level cause. One sees the differential causal impact of drift only by comparing populations of different sizes” (p. 556, see also pp. 563–564).

  8. Reisman and Forber’s exact formulation is as follows: “[Premise] 1. The manipulation condition. [Premise] 2. Manipulating the character of selection and drift can result in systematic changes to population-level dynamics. [Conclusion] Selection and drift are causes of population-level dynamics.” (2005, 1114) Reisman and Forber explicitly refer to population-level variables as causes when they claim: “we can manipulate the strength of drift in a population by manipulating the size of the population” (p. 1115). When they refer to the authors of the experiment they discuss, they write “[t]hey manipulate a population-level parameter to test how selection and drift interact to produce evolutionary change” (p. 1116).

  9. Note that there exists some heterogeneity in the genetic background of fruit flies. Thus, the environment is not homogenous from the point of view of the alleles of the population. This difference is crucial for the rest of the argument.

  10. In the example proposed by Dobzhansky and Pavlovsky, the measures of frequency are made on alleles, not individual organisms. Thus, an “individual” refers here to a token allele.

  11. Note, that using the binomial distribution implies the assumption of a founding population of unlimited size (equivalent to a drawing without replacement). If we were to release this assumption and have a source population with a finite size (equivalent to a drawing with replacement), the appropriate distribution would be a hypergeometric one. It can be shown that as the population size increases, the hypergeometric distribution tends toward a binomial one.

  12. This assumes that the variability in the genetic background is not neutral. Of course, such a manipulation would have consequence of a higher magnitude in a small than large population since the frequency of one allele is a small population is different from that of a large one. But that is beside the point.

  13. For more on the subtleties of the notion of invariance see Pocheville et al (2017).

  14. This point might look, at first glance, similar to the point made by the statisticalists and discussed in the introduction, that natural selection and drift are not causes of evolution because they are context dependent. The point here however is different. All causal relationships are to some extent context dependent, and following the criterion of invariance, the less context dependent relationship leads to better causal explanation. Thus, the point is not that context dependent relationships are not causal explanations as argued by the statisticalists.

  15. For a discussion on the notion of screening-off see Brandon (1990).

  16. We could, for instance, imagine that some quantum processes percolate up in a biological process and have consequences on reproductive outputs, as done by Glymour (2001).

  17. Needless to say, both deterministic and indeterministic natural selection/drift can be at play in a single population.

References

  • Ariew A, Rice C, Rohwer Y (2015) Autonomous-statistical explanations and natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 66(3):635–658

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J (1984) Chance and natural selection. Philos Sci 51(2):183–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F, Rosenberg A (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55(4):693–712

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2015) Distinguishing natural selection from other evolutionary processes in the evolution of altruism. Biol Theory 10(4):311–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2017) Explaining drift from a deterministic setting. Biol Theory 12(1):27–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1970) Genetics of the evolutionary process. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T, Pavlovsky O (1957) An experimental study of interaction between genetic drift and natural selection. Evolution 11:311–319

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T, Spassky NP (1962) Genetic drift and natural selection in experimental populations of Drosophila pseudoobscura. Proc Natl Acad Sci 48(2):148–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Forber P, Reisman K (2007) Can there be stochastic evolutionary causes? Philos Sci 74(5):616–627

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2005) Evolution. Sinauer Associates Inc, Sunerland, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour B (2001) Selection, indeterminism, and evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 68(4):518–535

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2012) The strategic gene. Biol Philos 27(4):461–479

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton M (2009) Population genetics. Wiley, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock C, Velasco J (2014) Evolutionary and Newtonian forces. Ergo Open Access J Philos 1

  • Huneman P (2014) Inscrutability and the opacity of natural selection and random genetic drift: distinguishing the epistemic and metaphysical aspects. Erkenntnis 80(3):491–518

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B, Riley MA, Feldman MW, Bohannan BJ (2002) Local dispersal promotes biodiversity in a real-life game of rock–paper–scissors. Nature 418(6894):171–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu Q, Bourrat P (2017) The evolutionary gene and the extended evolutionary synthesis. Br J Philos Sci. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axw035

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 99(2):55–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2009) Selection and causation. Philos Sci 76(2):201–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. Br J Philos Sci 57(4):627–653

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2016) Genetic drift. In: Zalta EN (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2016)

  • Northcott R (2010) Walsh on causes and evolution. Philos Sci 77(3):457–467

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2008) Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection—a philosophical analysis. Br J Philos Sci 59(3):319–351

    Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J (2016) A critical review of the statisticalist debate. Biol Philos 31(4):459–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J, Turner T, Allen C, Lloyd EA (2011) Why the causal view of fitness survives. Philos Sci 78(2):209–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2009) Causality: models, reasoning, and inference, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Plutynski A (2007) Drift: a historical and conceptual overview. Biol Theory 2:156–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville A, Griffiths PE, Stotz K (2017) Comparing causes—an information-theoretic approach to specificity, proportionality and stability. In: Leitgeb H, Niiniluoto I, Sober E, Seppälä P (eds) Proceedings of the 15th congress of logic, methodology and philosophy of science. College Publications, London, pp 250–275

  • Reisman K, Forber P (2005) Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philos Sci 72(5):1113–1123

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2001) Discussion note: indeterminism, probability, and randomness in evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 68(4):536–544

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A, Bouchard F (2005) Matthen and Ariew’s obituary for fitness: reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Biol Philos 20(2):343–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2008) A note on frequency dependence and the levels/units of selection. Biol Philos 23(2):217–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L, Sober E (2007) Epiphenomenalism—the do’s and the don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: From Greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 235–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2010) Evolutionary theory and the reality of macro-probabilities. In: Eells E, Fetzer JH (eds) The place of probability in science. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 133–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C (2004) Selection, drift, and the “Forces” of evolution. Philos Sci 71(4):550–570

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Kitcher P (1988) The return of the gene. J Philos 85(7):339–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2000) Chasing shadows: natural selection and adaptation. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 31(1):135–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74(3):281–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2010) Not a sure thing: fitness, probability, and causation. Philos Sci 77(2):147–171

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69(3):429–446

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Ariew A, Matthen M (2017) Four pillars of statisticalism. Philos Theory Biol 9(20170609)

  • Weber M (2001) Determinism, realism, and probability in evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 68(3):S213–S224

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2000) Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. Br J Philos Sci 51(2):197–254

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2010) Causation in biology: stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biol Philos 25(3):287–318

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2013) Causation and manipulability. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/causation-mani/

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am thankful to Paul Griffiths, Frans Jacobs, Charles Pence, Arnaud Pocheville, Joeri Witteveen and three anonymous reviewers for their comments on earlier versions of the manuscript. This research was supported under Australian Research Council’s Discovery Projects funding scheme (project number DP150102875) and a Macquarie University Research Fellowship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierrick Bourrat.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bourrat, P. Natural Selection and Drift as Individual-Level Causes of Evolution. Acta Biotheor 66, 159–176 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-018-9331-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-018-9331-1

Keywords

Navigation