Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Working time regulation, unequal lifetimes and fairness

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We examine the redistributive impact of working time regulations in an economy with unequal lifetimes. We first compare the laissez-faire equilibrium with the ex post egalitarian optimum, where the realized lifetime well-being of the worst off (usually the short-lived) is maximized, and show that, unlike the laissez-faire, this social optimum involves an increasing working time age profile and equalizes the realized lifetime well-being of the short-lived and the long-lived. We then examine whether working time regulations can compensate the short-lived. It is shown that uniform working time regulations cannot improve the situation of the short-lived with respect to the laissez-faire, and can only reduce well-being inequalities at the cost of making the short-lived worse off. However, age-specific regulations involving lower working time for the young and higher working time for the old make the short-lived better off, even though such regulations may not fully eradicate well-being inequalities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Askenazy (2013) for a survey of these studies.

  2. Holmlund and Pencavel (1988) and Friesen (2000) show that a reduction in the working time is associated with a significant rise in the hourly wage in countries such as Sweden, the Netherlands and Canada.

  3. Christensen et al. (2006) emphasize that about 1/4–1/3 of longevity inequalities are due to the genetic background, over which individuals have little control.

  4. For the sake of presentation, our results are here given only for the case of affluent economies (where productivity is sufficiently high so that the long-lived is better off than the short-lived). See the manuscript for the results concerning poor economies (where productivity is so low that the long-lived is necessarily worse off than the short-lived).

  5. The reason why imposing a uniform working time age profile cannot increase consumption or well-being at the young age in comparison to the laissez-faire is that the intratemporal arbitrage between labor and consumption is already solved optimally at the laissez-faire.

  6. The capacity of age-specific working time regulations to bring well-being equality is here limited by the upper bound on the labor supply of the surviving old.

  7. We abstract here from the childhood period, which is not relevant for the issue at stake.

  8. We abstract from the retirement decision. See Fleurbaey et al. (2016) on the selection of fair retirement age under fixed working time.

  9. Throughout this paper, we assume, without loss of generality, that \(w>\bar{c} \). This assumption allows us to avoid extreme cases that are irrelevant for the issue at stake.

  10. Indeed, substituting for constant consumption and labor profiles into the intertemporal budget constraint yields:

    $$\begin{aligned} c^{LF}(1+\pi )=\ell ^{LF}w(1+\pi ). \end{aligned}$$

    Thus the life expectancy \(1+\pi \) can be simplified from both sides, making the laissez-faire consumption independent from \(\pi \). But given the “final equivalence of labor and utility”, if consumption is independent from \(\pi \) , labor supply is also independent from \(\pi \).

  11. Note that, since per period utility is here constant along the lifecycle, it follows that the utility of a short-lived individual \(U^{SL}\) is here exactly equal to the gain in lifetime utility when the agent survives to the next period (i.e. \(U^{LL}-U^{SL}\)). This equality is due to the conjunction of three assumptions: no pure time preferences, age-independent labor disutility and a perfect annuity market. This implies that, at the laissez-faire equilibrium, per period utility is the same at each period of life. We come back on this point later on in the manuscript.

  12. In the Appendix we derive, under standard functional forms for \(u(\cdot )\) and \(v\left( \cdot \right) \), the threshold for the wage rate w beyond which the long-lived are better off than the short-lived.

  13. Note that, in order to do justice to the idea of compensating the worst-off, one cannot, in the present context, rely on a utilitarian social welfare function, since, as we showed in Sect. 3, this social criterion legitimates the laissez-faire and the resulting inequalities in realized lifetime well-being between short-lived and long-lived individuals.

  14. In particular, the fact that a prematurely dead person expected to have a long life does not seem to be a relevant piece of information to assess his lifetime well-being.

  15. The underlying intuition goes as follows. At the ex post egalitarian optimum, consumption and working time profiles are chosen so as to maximize the well-being of the short-lived, whereas at the laissez-faire, consumption and working time profiles are chosen in such a way as to maximize a weighted sum of the well-being of the short-lived and the well-being at the old age. Given that the resource constraint is the same in the two optimization problems, the short-lived must be better off at the ex post egalitarian optimum than at the laissez-faire.

  16. By “uniform” working time regulations, we mean regulations that consist in imposing flat working time profiles, i.e., a constant quantity of worked hours along the life cycle (i.e., \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=\bar{\ell }_{o}=\bar{\ell }\) ). Non-uniform (age-specific) working time regulations are studied in Sect. 6.

  17. It should be stressed here that \(\bar{\ell }\) does not denote an upper bound for the number of hours worked, but the exact number of hours worked. This assumption simplifies the presentation of results, and is also close to real economies where individuals generally work full time, i.e. at the level of the uniform regulation.

  18. Given that the policy instrument considered here (a uniform working time \( \bar{\ell }\)) is extremely basic, one can regard this social planning problem as a kind of “third-best problem” (since this involves strong restrictions on available policy instruments).

  19. Such a dilemma is a direct consequence of both consumption smoothing and the restriction put on the instruments, that is, it is imposed that \(\bar{\ell }\) must be the same for all workers, independently of whether these are young or old.

  20. One can regard the social planning problem of Sect. 6 as a “second-best problem” since the set of policy instruments \(\left( \bar{\ell }_{y},\bar{\ell }_{o}\right) \) is here less constrained that in the problem of Sect. 5.

  21. Note, however, that, contrary to what happens under uniform working time regulations (Sect. 5), consumption smoothing does not imply here that utility per period of life is constant along the life cycle, since labor time varies with the age.

  22. The working time is expressed in hours per week. Note that the maximum working time equals 80 h per week, which corresponds to 5 days of 16 h of daily work (leaving only 8 h for sleep and daily activities).

  23. This coincides with the corner solution \(\ell _{o}^{*}=1\) in Sect. 4. As shown on Fig. 1, this corner solution arises for \(\beta \) lower than 15. For \(\beta >15\), there is an interior solution, corresponding to \(\ell _{o}^{*}<1\) in the model.

  24. If social recognition from labor matters a lot, and if this social recognition is only achieved for a sufficiently large working time, this would probably restrict the extent of optimal differentiation of working time between the young and the old.

References

  • Askenazy P (2013) Working time regulation in France from 1996 to 2012. Camb J Econ 37(2):323–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker G, Philipson T, Soares R (2005) The quantity and the quality of life and the evolution of world inequality. Am Econ Rev 95(1):277–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campanella T (1602) Civitas Solis. The City of the Sun, Translated by T. Halliday, Anodos Books, 2017 (English version)

  • Chemin M, Wasmer E (2009) Using Alsace-Moselle local laws to build a difference-in-differences estimation strategy of the employment effects of the 35-hour workweek regulation in France. J Labor Econ 27(4):487–524

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen K, Johnson T, Vaupel J (2006) The quest for genetic determinants of human longevity: challenges and insights. Nat Rev Genet 7:436–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crépon B, Kramarz F (2002) Employed 40 hours or not-employed 39: lessons from the 1982 mandatory reduction of the workweek. J Political Econ 110(6):1355–1389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crépon B, Leclair M, Roux S (2004) RTT, productivit é et emploi: nouvelles estimations sur données d’entreprises. Économie et Statistique 376(7):55–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M (2008) Fairness, responsibility and welfare. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Leroux ML, Ponthiere G (2014) Compensating the dead. J Math Econ 51(C):28–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Leroux ML, Pestieau P, Ponthiere G (2016) Fair retirement under risky lifetime. Int Econ Rev 57(1):177–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2004) Compensation and responsibility. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, 1st edn, vol 2, chapter 22, pp 507–604

  • Fleurbaey M, Ponthiere G (2013) Prevention against equality? J Public Econ 103(C):68–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friesen J (2000) Overtime pay regulation and weekly hours of work in Canada. Labour Econ 8:691–720

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goux D, Maurin E, Petrongolo B (2011) Worktime regulations and spousal labour supply. IZA Discussion Paper 5639

  • Holmlund B, Pencavel J (1988) The determination of wages, employment and work-hours in an economy with centralised wage-setting: Sweden, 1950–83. Econ J 98:1105–1126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt J (1999) Has work-sharing worked in Germany? Q J Econ 114:117–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jevons WS (1871) The theory of political economy. Penguin Classics, London

    Google Scholar 

  • More T (1516) Utopia. In: Surtz E, Hester J (eds) The yale edition of the complete works of St. thomas more. vol 4, 1964 (English version)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregory Ponthiere.

Additional information

We would like to thank K. Behrens, V. Barham, P. De Donder, L. Larue, J. Martin, F. Moizeau, P. Pestieau, M. Yazbeck and D. Zwarthoed for their comments on this paper. We are also grateful to two anonymous referees for their remarks and suggestions on this manuscript.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Proposition 1

The FOCs of the individual’s problem are:

$$\begin{aligned} \pi u^{\prime }(c)= & {} \pi u^{\prime }(d) \\ wu^{\prime }(c)= & {} v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})+\rho _{y}-\varphi _{y} \\ wu^{\prime }(c)= & {} v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})+\frac{\rho _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{ \varphi _{o}}{\pi } \end{aligned}$$

as well as conditions \(\rho _{y}\ge 0,1-\ell _{y}\ge 0\); \(\rho _{o}\ge 0,1-\ell _{o}\ge 0\); \(\varphi _{y}\ge 0,\ell _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\varphi _{o}\ge 0,\ell _{o}\ge 0\) with complementary slackness.

We obviously have, from the first FOC, \(c=d\). Regarding the working time profile, several cases can arise.

  • If \(0<\ell _{y},\ell _{o}<1\), we have \(\rho _{y}=\rho _{o}=\varphi _{y}=\varphi _{o}=0.\) The FOCs become \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(\ell _{y}) \) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})\). Hence we have \(0<\ell _{y}=\ell _{o}<1\).

  • If \(\ell _{y}=0\), we have \(\rho _{y}=0\) and \(\varphi _{y}\ge 0\). The second FOC becomes: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(0)-\varphi _{y}\iff wu^{\prime }(c)=-\varphi _{y}\). Given that \(u^{\prime }(c)>0\), that case is not possible.

  • If \(\ell _{o}=0\), we have \(\rho _{o}=0\) and \(\varphi _{o}\ge 0\). The third FOC becomes: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(0)-\frac{\varphi _{o}}{\pi } \iff wu^{\prime }(c)=-\frac{\varphi _{o}}{\pi }\). Again that case is not possible.

  • If \(\ell _{y}=1\), we have \(\rho _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\varphi _{y}=0\). The second FOC becomes: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\rho _{y}\).

    • If \(0<\ell _{o}<1\), so that \(\rho _{o}=\varphi _{o}=0\), we then have \( wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\rho _{y}\) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})\), which implies \(v^{\prime }(1)+\rho _{y}=v^{\prime }(\ell _{o}) \). That case is not possible.

    • If \(\ell _{o}=1\), so that \(\rho _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\varphi _{o}=0\), we then have: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\rho _{y}\) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\rho _{o}\). That case is possible.

  • If \(\ell _{o}=1\), we have \(\rho _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\varphi _{o}=0\). The third FOC becomes: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\frac{\rho _{o}}{\pi }\). If \(0<\ell _{y}<1\), so that \(\rho _{y}=\varphi _{y}=0\), we then have \( wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})\) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+ \frac{\rho _{o}}{\pi }\iff v^{\prime }(1)+\frac{\rho _{o}}{\pi }=v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})\). That case is not possible.

In sum, only two cases can arise: either \(0<\ell _{y}=\ell _{o}<1\) or \(\ell _{y}=\ell _{o}=1\). Given that consumption is smoothed, we have \(c=\ell w+\pi \ell w-\pi c\), implying \(c=d=w\ell \). Hence whether one case arises or the other depends on whether \(wu^{\prime }(w)\gtrless v^{\prime }(1)\). If \( wu^{\prime }(w)<v^{\prime }(1)\), the laissez-faire equilibrium is interior and we have \(0<\ell _{y}=\ell _{o}<1\). On the contrary, when \(wu^{\prime }(w)\ge v^{\prime }(1)\), we have the corner solution \(\ell _{y}=\ell _{o}=1\).

1.2 Analytical example: the threshold for w

In order to discuss whether the long-lived is better off than the short-lived at the laissez-faire, let us take the following functional forms for \(u\left( \cdot \right) \) and \(v\left( \cdot \right) \):

$$\begin{aligned} u(c)=\frac{\left( w\ell \right) ^{1-\sigma }}{1-\sigma }-\alpha \quad \text { and }\quad v\left( \ell \right) =\frac{\beta \ell ^{2}}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

The condition for optimal working time \(wu^{\prime }(w\ell )=v^{\prime }(\ell )\) and the egalitarian condition \(u(w\ell )=v(\ell )\) can be rewritten as, respectively:

$$\begin{aligned} w\left( w\ell \right) ^{-\sigma }=\beta \ell \iff \ell =\left( \frac{ w^{1-\sigma }}{\beta }\right) ^{\frac{1}{1+\sigma }}\quad \text { and }\quad \frac{\left( w\ell \right) ^{1-\sigma }}{1-\sigma }-\alpha =\frac{\beta \ell ^{2}}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Hence substituting for the first equation in the second, we obtain:

$$\begin{aligned} U^{LL}\gtrless U^{SL}\iff w\gtrless \left[ \frac{\alpha }{\beta ^{\frac{ \sigma -1}{1+\sigma }}\left[ \frac{1}{1-\sigma }-\frac{1}{2}\right] }\right] ^{\frac{1+\sigma }{2(1-\sigma )}}. \end{aligned}$$

The RHS consists of the threshold for the wage beyond which the long-lived is better off than the short-lived. The threshold depends on \(\alpha \), \( \beta \) and \(\sigma \). The higher the wage is, the more likely it is that the LHS exceeds the RHS, implying that \(U^{LL}>U^{SL}\).

1.3 Proof of Proposition 2

The FOCs of the social planner’s problem are:

$$\begin{aligned} \pi u^{\prime }(c)= & {} \mu u^{\prime }(d) \\ wu^{\prime }(c)= & {} v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y} \\ \pi wu^{\prime }(c)= & {} \mu v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})+\kappa _{o}-\gamma _{o} \end{aligned}$$

as well as the conditions \(\mu \ge 0,u(d)-v(\ell _{o})\ge 0\); \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0,1-\ell _{y}\ge 0\);\(\kappa _{o}\ge 0,1-\ell _{o}\ge 0\); \( \gamma _{y}\ge 0,\ell _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{o}\ge 0,\ell _{o}\ge 0\) with complementary slackness.

  1. 1.

    Let us suppose that the egalitarian constraint is satisfied, so that \( \mu \ge 0\) and\(u(d)-v(\ell _{o})=0\).

    1. (a)

      In the interior case (\(0<\ell _{o},\ell _{y}<1\)), we have \(\kappa _{y}=\kappa _{o}=\gamma _{y}=\gamma _{o}=0\), so that: \(v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})\). We thus have either an increasing or a decreasing consumption profile, depending on whether \(\frac{ \mu }{\pi }\lessgtr 1\).

    2. (b)

      If now \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) so that \(\ell _{y}=1\), and \(\kappa _{o}=0\) so that \(\ell _{o}<1\). In that situation, we have \(\gamma _{y}=0\) (since \( \ell _{y}=1\)). We then have: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}\) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})-\gamma _{o}\implies v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }\).

      • If \(\gamma _{o}=0\), i.e. \(\ell _{o}>0\), two cases can arise depending on whether \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }\gtrless 1\). (1) If \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\), we have a contradiction since the above equality would imply \(v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})>v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}\) and thus \(\ell _{o}>1\). That corner case \( \left( \ell _{y}=1,\ell _{o}<1\right) \) is not possible in affluent economies. (2) When \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }>1\), \(\left( \ell _{y}=1,\ell _{o}<1\right) \) is possible.

      • If \(\gamma _{o}\ge 0\), \(\ell _{o}=0\), we have \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(0)-\gamma _{o}\) which is possible only if \( \mu /\pi >1\) (i.e. poor economy). But the case \(\left( \ell _{y}=1,\ell _{o}=0\right) \) is not possible when \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\) (affluent economy).

    3. (c)

      If \(\kappa _{y}=0\) so that \(\ell _{y}<1\), and \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) and \( \ell _{o}=1\). We then have that \(\gamma _{o}=0\) and \(wu^{\prime }(c)=\frac{ \mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(1)+\frac{\kappa }{\pi }=v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})-\gamma _{y}\).

      • If \(\gamma _{y}=0\) implying \(\ell _{y}>0\), when \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }>1\), we have a contradiction. That case \(\left( \ell _{y}<1,\ell _{o}=1\right) \) is thus not possible. But when \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\) (affluent economies) that case \(\left( \ell _{y}<1,\ell _{o}=1\right) \) is possible.

      • If \(\gamma _{y}\ge 0\) implying \(\ell _{y}=0\), we have \(\frac{\mu }{ \pi }v^{\prime }(1)+\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }=v^{\prime }(0)-\gamma _{y}\), which is impossible.

    4. (d)

      Consider now the double corner case, where \(\ell _{o}=\ell _{y}=1\), so that \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) , \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{y}=\gamma _{o}=0 \). We then have \(wu^{\prime }(c)=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(1)+ \frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }=v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}\). When \(\frac{\mu }{\pi } >1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}>\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). When \(\frac{\mu }{\pi } <1\), we have the opposite. That case is possible.

    5. (e)

      Consider now the double corner case, where \(\ell _{o}=\ell _{y}=0\), so that \(\kappa _{o}=\kappa _{y}=0\) and \(\gamma _{y},\gamma _{o}>0\). This implies \(c=d=0.\) But the egalitarian constrain would then become \(u(0)=v(0)\) , which is impossible, since the LHS is negative and the RHS is zero. The case \(\left( \ell _{y}=0,\ell _{o}=0\right) \) is not possible here.

    6. (f)

      Consider now the case where \(\ell _{y}=0\) so that \(\kappa _{y}=0\) and \( \gamma _{y}\ge 0\). We have: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})+\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }=v^{\prime }(0)-\gamma _{y}\). If \(0<\ell _{o}<1\), \(\kappa _{o}=\gamma _{o}=0\), so that we have \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\ell _{o})=-\gamma _{y}\). This is not possible.

    7. (g)

      Consider now the case where \(\ell _{o}=0\) so that \(\kappa _{o}=0\) and \( \gamma _{o}\ge 0\). We have: \(wu^{\prime }(c)=-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi } =v^{\prime }(\ell _{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y}\). If \(0<\ell _{y}<1\), \( \kappa _{y}=\gamma _{y}=0\), implying \(-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }=v^{\prime }(\ell _{y}).\) which is not possible either.

  2. 2.

    Suppose now that the egalitarian constraint does not hold so that \(\mu =0\). The FOC for d is now strictly negative and equal to \(-\pi u^{\prime }(c)\) which implies that \(d=0\). However, under the egalitarian constraint, we need to have \(u(0)-v(\ell _o)>0\) which is not possible since \(u(0)<0\). Hence, this case is not possible.

1.4 Proof of Proposition 4

The FOCs of the social planner’s problem are:

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ wu^{\prime }(w\bar{\ell })-v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell })\right] \left( 1+\mu \right) =\kappa -\gamma \end{aligned}$$

as well as the conditions \(\mu \ge 0,u\left( w\bar{\ell }\right) -v\left( \bar{\ell }\right) \ge 0\); \(\gamma \ge 0,\bar{\ell }\ge 0\) and \(\kappa \ge 0,1-\bar{\ell }\ge 0\) with complementary slackness.

  1. 1.

    Suppose the egalitarian constraint holds so that \(\mu \ge 0\) and \( u\left( w\bar{\ell }\right) =v\left( \bar{\ell }\right) \). The FOC becomes \( \left[ u^{\prime }(c)w-v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell })\right] =\frac{\kappa -\gamma }{1+\mu }\). For any interior value of \(\bar{\ell }\) (i.e. \(\gamma =\kappa =0\)), we would have \(u^{\prime }(w\bar{\ell })w=v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell })\) which cannot hold at the same time as the egalitarian constraint (\(u(w\bar{\ell } )=v(\bar{\ell })\)). The same reasoning applies when \(\bar{\ell }=0\) (i.e. \( \gamma \ge 0\) and \(\kappa =0\)) and when \(\bar{\ell }=1\) (i.e. \(\gamma =0\) and \(\kappa \ge 0\)). Hence, the egalitarian constraint can never be binding.

  2. 2.

    Suppose that the egalitarian constraint does not hold, so that we have \(\mu =0\) and \(u\left( w\bar{\ell }\right) >v\left( \bar{\ell }\right) \). The FOC becomes: \(\left[ u^{\prime }(w\bar{\ell })w-v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }) \right] =\kappa -\gamma \). If \(\bar{\ell }\) is interior, we have \(\kappa =\gamma =0\) and the solution is given by \(u^{\prime }(w\bar{\ell } )w=v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell })\) as in the laissez-faire equilibrium. If \(\bar{ \ell }=0\), we have \(\kappa =0\) and \(\gamma \ge 0\), so that \(u^{\prime }(c)w=-\gamma \) which is not possible since \(u^{\prime }(c)>0\). If \(\bar{\ell }=1\), we have \(\kappa \ge 0\) and \(\gamma =0\), so that \(\left[ u^{\prime }(w)w-v^{\prime }(1)\right] =\kappa \). That case is possible. Thus we have either \(0<\bar{\ell }<1\) or \(\bar{\ell }=1\).

Inequalities in realized lifetime well-being are: \(U^{LL}-U^{SL}=u(w\bar{\ell })-v(\bar{\ell })\). To reduce \(U^{LL}-U^{SL}\), the government must choose \( \tilde{\ell }\ne \bar{\ell }\). We would then have: \(u(w\tilde{\ell })-v(\tilde{ \ell })<u(w\bar{\ell })-v(\bar{\ell })\). Thus, there would be a reduction of \( U^{LL}-U^{SL}\) with respect to the optimal regulation (and also with respect to the laissez-faire). But this reduction in inequalities would be achieved at the cost of making the short-lived worst-off than at the laissez-faire since his utility would now be \(u(w\tilde{\ell })-v(\tilde{\ell })\) instead of \(u(w\bar{\ell })-v(\bar{\ell })\).

1.5 Proof of Proposition 5

The FOCs of the social planner’s problem are:

$$\begin{aligned} u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }(1+\mu )= & {} v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y} \\ u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }(1+\mu )= & {} \frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\bar{ \ell }_{o})+\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi } \end{aligned}$$

as well as the conditions \(\mu \ge 0,u\left( w\frac{\bar{\ell }_{y}+\pi \bar{ \ell }_{o}}{1+\pi }\right) -v(\bar{\ell }_{o})\ge 0\); \(\gamma _{y}\ge 0,\bar{ \ell }_{y}\ge 0\); \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0,1-\bar{\ell }_{y}\ge 0\); \(\gamma _{o}\ge 0,\bar{\ell }_{o}\ge 0\) and \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0,1-\bar{\ell }_{o}\ge 0\) with complementary slackness.

  1. 1.

    Take the case where the egalitarian constraint is satisfied. We have \( \mu \ge 0\) and \(u\left( w\frac{\bar{\ell }_{y}+\pi \bar{\ell }_{o}}{1+\pi } \right) -v(\bar{\ell }_{o})=0.\)

    1. (a)

      If \(0<\bar{\ell }_{o},\bar{\ell }_{y}<1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}=\kappa _{o}=\gamma _{y}=\gamma _{o}=v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})\) and \(u^{\prime }(c) \frac{w}{1+\pi }(1+\mu )=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{o})\). When \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\), we have thus \(v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{o})>v^{\prime }( \bar{\ell }_{y})\), implying \(\bar{\ell }_{o}>\bar{\ell }_{y}\). When \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }>1\), the opposite holds.

    2. (b)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=0\), we have \(\kappa _{y}=0\) and \(\gamma _{y}\ge 0\) . We have \(u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }(1+\mu )=v^{\prime }(0)-\gamma _{y} \frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{o})+\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{ \gamma _{o}}{\pi }\). If \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\), we have a contradiction: the egalitarian constraint cannot hold as \(u(0)\ne v(0)\). If \(0<\bar{\ell } _{o}<1 \), we have \(\kappa _{o}=0\) and \(\gamma _{o}=0\), so that \(-\gamma _{y}= \frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{o})\) which is not possible. If \( \bar{\ell }_{o}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{o}=0\), so that we have \(-\gamma _{y}=\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(1)+\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is not possible either.

    3. (c)

      Using the same reasoning as in (b) we can show that \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\) is never possible.

    4. (d)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=1\) and \(\bar{\ell }_{o}<1\), we have \( \gamma _y=\gamma _o=0\), \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\kappa _{o}=0\). FOCs become \( u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }=\frac{\kappa _{y}+v^{\prime }(1)}{1+\mu }= \frac{\frac{\mu }{\pi }v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{o})}{1+\mu }\). If \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\), a contradiction is reached. If \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }>1\), that case is possible.

    5. (e)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}<1\) and \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=1\), we have \( \gamma _y=\gamma _o=0\), \(\kappa _{y}=0,\) and \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0.\) FOCs become \( u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }=\frac{v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})}{1+\mu }= \frac{\kappa _{o}+\mu v^{\prime }(1)}{\pi (1+\mu )}\). If \(\frac{\mu }{\pi } >1 \), that case is not possible. If \(\frac{\mu }{\pi }<1\), that case is possible.

    6. (f)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=\bar{\ell }_{o}=1\), we have \(\gamma _y=\gamma _o=0\), \( \kappa _{y},\kappa _{o}\ge 0.\) FOCs become: \(u^{\prime }(c)(1+\mu )\frac{w}{ 1+\pi }=\kappa _{y}+v^{\prime }(1)=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }+\frac{\mu }{\pi } v^{\prime }(1)\). That case is possible.

  2. 2.

    Take now the case where the egalitarian constraint does not hold. We have \(\mu =0\) and \(u\left( w\frac{\bar{\ell }_{y}+\pi \bar{\ell }_{o}}{1+\pi } \right) -v(\bar{\ell }_{o})>0\).

    In that case, the FOCs become: \(u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }-v^{\prime }( \bar{\ell }_{y})=\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y}\) and \(u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w\pi }{ 1+\pi }=\kappa _{o}-\gamma _{o}\). Hence \(u^{\prime }(c)\frac{w}{1+\pi }=v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi } -\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }\).

    1. (a)

      Take the case where both \(\bar{\ell }_{y}\) and \(\bar{\ell }_{o}\) are interior. We then have \(v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})=0\) leading to \(\bar{\ell } _{y}=0\). A contradiction.

    2. (b)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=0\), we have \(\kappa _{y}=0\) and \(\gamma _{y}\ge 0\) . This leads to \(-\gamma _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{ \pi }\). The case where \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\) is not possible as it would not satisfy the egalitarian constraint (\(u\left( 0\right) -v(0)<0\) in that case). If \(0<\bar{\ell }_{o}<1\), we have \(\kappa _{o}=\gamma _{o}=0\). This leads to \(-\gamma _{y}=0\). That case is impossible. If \(\bar{\ell } _{o}=1 \), we have \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{o}=0\). This leads to \( -\gamma _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is impossible.

    3. (c)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{y}=0\) . This leads to \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }-\frac{ \gamma _{o}}{\pi }\). If \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\), we have \(\kappa _{o}=0\) and \( \gamma _{o}\ge 0\). This leads to \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is impossible. If \(0<\bar{\ell }_{o}<1\), we have \( \kappa _{o}=\gamma _{o}=0\). This leads to \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=0\). That case is impossible. If \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{o}=0\). This leads to \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is possible.

    4. (d)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\), we have \(\kappa _{o}=0\) and \(\gamma _{o}\ge 0\) . We have \(v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y}=-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }\). From (b), we know that \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=\bar{\ell }_{o}=0\) is not possible. If \(0<\bar{\ell }_{y}<1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}=\gamma _{y}=0\). We have \(v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})=-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is impossible. If \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) and \( \gamma _{y}=0\). We have \(v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=-\frac{\gamma _{o}}{\pi } \). That case is impossible.

    5. (e)

      If \(\bar{\ell }_{o}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{o}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{o}=0\) . We have \(v^{\prime }(\bar{\ell }_{y})+\kappa _{y}-\gamma _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }.\) From (b), we know that \(\bar{\ell }_{y}=0\) is impossible. If \(0< \bar{\ell }_{y}<1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}=\gamma _{y}=0\). We have \(v^{\prime }( \bar{\ell }_{y})=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is possible. If \(\bar{ \ell }_{y}=1\), we have \(\kappa _{y}\ge 0\) and \(\gamma _{y}=0\). We have \( v^{\prime }(1)+\kappa _{y}=\frac{\kappa _{o}}{\pi }\). That case is possible.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Leroux, ML., Ponthiere, G. Working time regulation, unequal lifetimes and fairness. Soc Choice Welf 51, 437–464 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1123-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1123-7

Navigation