Skip to main content
Log in

Power at general equilibrium

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We integrate individual power in groups into general equilibrium models with endogenous group formation. We distinguish between real power (utility gain from being in groups) and power-related parameters in group decision making, like utilitarian welfare weights in the case of welfare maximization or relative bargaining power in Nash bargaining. We find that higher “parametric power” does not necessarily translate into higher equilibrium utility or higher real power. One reason is that induced price changes may offset the group member’s increased influence and the resulting benefits. A second reason is that the group may dissolve when a group member gains too much influence, because other members can exercise the option to leave. We also show that maximal real power can be compatible with Pareto efficiency. We further identify circumstances when changes of power in one group do not impact on other groups. Finally, we establish existence of competitive equilibria, including equilibria where some individual enjoys real power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The focus of Gersbach and Haller (2011a) lies on the existence and optimality of CEFE (competitive equilibrium with free exit, the concept adopted in the current paper) and the comparison of CEFE and CEFH (a more demanding equilibrium concept), while power—the central theme of the current investigation—is only treated in passing. An overview of our approach to group formation and competitive markets is given in Gersbach and Haller (2017). The book chapter on power in general equilibrium reports on substantially different result. It primarily but not exclusively deals with exogenous household structures and price-independent outside options and summarizes the findings in Gersbach and Haller (2009).

  2. See Dowding (2017) and Hindmoor and McGeechan (2013) for further discussion.

  3. The notation “>” means in this context that \(\mathcal {U}_i(\mathbf {x'};P') \ge \mathcal {U}_i (\mathbf {x};P)\) for all \(i \in I\) and \(\mathcal {U}_i(\mathbf {x'};P') > \mathcal {U}_i (\mathbf {x};P)\) for at least one \(i \in I\).

  4. In Gersbach and Haller (2001), we distinguish between fixed and variable household structures and, accordingly, between constrained and full Pareto optimality. The concept adopted here corresponds to full Pareto optimality.

  5. Another advantage of group formation could be group production. For instance, in a reduced form of group production, group formation could simply augment the initial endowment with resources: the collective endowment of a multi-member group could exceed the sum of the individual endowments of group members, which constitutes a positive endowment externality in the taxonomy of Gori and Villanacci (2011).

  6. Gersbach and Haller (2011a) employ a different notion of large group advantage.

  7. This is reminiscent of the observation by Pycia (2012) that complementarities among some individuals within a group may benefit other members of the group.

  8. Pycia cites Baker et al. (2008) who reported that interviews with practitioners involved in the formation of alliances (coalitions) among firms led them to conclude that the lack of flexibility in dividing payoffs that accrue directly to firms in an alliance—rather than to the alliance itself—is one of two main factors determining the form and performance of alliances. In what they heard from practitioners, the inflexible sharing of payoffs played a markedly larger role than the inadequate specific investments identified as a source of holdup by Grossman and Hart (1986) and Hart and Moore (1990), and studied by the rich literature on the theory of the firm.

  9. That is, if for instance members h1 and g1 of two different groups \(g\in \widehat{P}\) and \(h\in \widehat{P}\) formed a new two-person group, both members would experience negative group externalities.

  10. This is guaranteed if the endowments of all individuals with the numéraire good are sufficiently large. The assumption allows us to work with the entire set of first-order conditions.

References

  • Aghion P, Tirole J (1997) Formal and real authority in organizations. J Polit Econ 105:1–5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apps P, Rees R (2009) Public economics and the household. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker GP, Gibbons R, Murphy J (2008) Strategic alliances: bridges between ‘islands of conscious power’. J Jpn Int Econ 22:146–163

  • Banerjee S, Konishi H, Sönmez T (2001) Core in a simple coalition formation game. Soc Choice Welfare 18:135–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogomolnaia A, Jackson MO (2002) The stability of hedonic coalition structures. Games Econ Behav 38(2):201–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole HL, Prescott EC (1997) Valuation equilibrium with clubs. J Econ Theory 74:19–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowding K (2017) Power, luck and freedom. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ellickson B (1979) Competitive equilibrium with local public goods. J Econ Theory 21:46–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellickson B, Grodal B, Scotchmer S, Zame WR (1999) Clubs and the market. Econometrica 67:1185–1218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellickson B, Grodal B, Scotchmer S, Zame WR (2001) Clubs and the market: large finite economies. J Econ Theory 101:40–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal LS, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2001) Collective decisions and competitive markets. Rev Econ Stud 68:347–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2009) Bargaining power and equilibrium consumption. Soc Choice Welfare 33(4):665–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2010) Club theory and household formation. J Math Econ 46:715–724

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2011a) Competitive markets, collective decisions and group formation. J Econ Theory 146:275–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2011b) Bargaining cum voice. Soc Choice Welfare 36:199–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2013) A human relations paradox. Math Soc Sci 65:154–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach H, Haller H (2017) Groups and markets: general equilibrium with multi-member households. Springer, Cham

  • Gilles RP, Scotchmer S (1997) Decentralization in replicated club economies with multiple private goods. J Econ Theory 72:363–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilles RP, Scotchmer S (1998) Topics in public economics: theoretical and applied analysis. In: Pines D, Sadka E, Zilcha I (eds) Decentralization in club economies: how multiple private goods matter, vol 5. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gori M, Villanacci A (2011) A bargaining model in general equilibrium. Econ Theor 46:327–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg J, Weber S (1986) Strong Tiebout equilibrium under restricted preferences domain. J Econ Theory 38:101–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossman SJ, Hart OD (1986) The costs and benefits of ownership: a theory of vertical and lateral integration. J Polit Econ 94:691–719

  • Guesnerie R, Oddou C (1981) Second best taxation as a game. J Econ Theory 25:67–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haller H (2000) Group decisions and equilibrium efficiency. Int Econ Rev 41(4):835–847

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart O, Moore J (1990) Property rights and the nature of the firm. J Polit Econ 98:1119–1158

  • Hindmoor A, McGeechan J (2013) Luck, systematic luck and business power: lucky all the way down or trying hard to get what it wants without trying? Polit Stud 61:834–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman AO (1970) Exit, voice, and loyality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Konishi H, Le Breton M, Weber S (1997) Pure strategy Nash equilibrium in a group formation game with positive externalities. Games Econ Behav 21:161–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konishi H, Le Breton M, Weber S (1998) Equilibrium in a finite local public goods economy. J Econ Theory 79:224–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makowski L, Ostroy JM, Segal U (1999) Efficient incentive compatible economies are perfectly competitive. J Econ Theory 85:169–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pycia M (2012) Stability and preference alignment in matching and coalition formation. Econometrica 80:323–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS, Shubik M (1971) The assignment game I: the core. Int J Game Theory 1:111–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wooders MH (1988) Stability of jurisdiction structures in economies with local public goods. Math Soc Sci 15:29–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wooders MH (1989) A Tiebout theorem. Math Soc Sci 18:33–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wooders MH (1997) Equivalence of Lindahl equilibrium with participation prices and the core. Econ Theor 9:115–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans Haller.

Additional information

A precursor has appeared as “Exit and Power in General Equilibrium”, CESifo Working Paper, No. 2369. We are grateful to Marc Fleurbaey, an associate editor and two referees for instructive comments and suggestions. We thank Elias Aptus, Clive Bell, Pierre-André Chiappori, Egbert Dierker, Bryan Ellickson, Theresa Fahrenberger, Volker Hahn, Martin Hellwig, Benny Moldovanu, Martin Scheffel, Klaus Schmidt, Bill Zame, and seminar participants in Bielefeld, Bonn, Basel, Berlin, Heidelberg and UCLA for helpful comments.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 3

Recall that for \(i\in I\) and \(P\in \mathcal{P}\), P(i) denotes the group to which i belongs in the group structure P.

First, we show that \((\mathbf {x} ; P^*)\) is a Pareto optimal allocation. For suppose not. Then there exists a feasible allocation \((\mathbf {y} ; P)\) that Pareto dominates \((\mathbf {x} ; P^*)\): \(U_i(y_i; P(i))> U_i(x_i; P^*(i))\) for some \(i\in I\) and \(U_i(y_i; P(i)) \ge U_i(x_i; P^*(i))\) for all \(i\in I\). Since \((p, \mathbf {x})\) is a competitive equilibrium of the pure exchange economy \((U_i^c, \omega _{\{i\}})_{i\in I}\) and consumers are locally non-satiated, \(\mathbf {x}\) is a Pareto optimal allocation of the pure exchange economy. Therefore, if it is the case that \(U_i^c(y_i) > U_i^c(x_i)\) for some i, then there exists \(j\ne i\) with \(U_j^c(y_j) < U_j^c(x_j)\) and, consequently, \(U^g_j(P(j))> U_j^g(P^*(j))\) (because \((\mathbf {y} ; P)\) Pareto dominates \((\mathbf {x} ; P^*)\)). If it is the case that \(U_i^c(y_i) \le U_i^c(x_i)\) for all i, then \(U^g_j(P(j))> U_j^g(P^*(j))\) for some j. In any case, \(U^g_j(P(j))> U_j^g(P^*(j))\) for some j. But then, by Fact 1 (i) there exists an optimal group structure \(P'\) based solely on group preferences such that \(U_j^g(P'(j))\ge U^g_j(P(j))> U_j^g(P^*(j))\) and, consequently, \(P'\ne P^*\), contradicting (iii).

Second, we show that \((p, \mathbf {x}; P^*)\) is a CEFE. Because of pure group externalities, (i) and (ii), the first two conditions for a CEFE hold. Moreover for \(i\in I\):

  1. (a)

    Since \((p, \mathbf {x})\) is a competitive equilibrium of the pure exchange economy \((U_i^c, \omega _{\{i\}})_{i\in I}\), \(x_i\) is an optimal consumption bundle in i’s budget set.

  2. (b)

    Since \(P^*\) is the unique optimal group structure solely based on group preferences, \(U_i^g(\{i\})\le U_i^g(P^*(i))\), by Fact 1 (i).

Hence i cannot fare better as a one-person group. Thus the third condition for a CEFE holds as well.

Third, we show that there does not exist another CEFE in which real power is higher for some individuals in their respective groups and not lower for any individual. Namely, suppose that there exists a CEFE \((p', \mathbf {y}; P')\) in which real power is higher for some individuals and not lower for any individual than in \((p, \mathbf {x}; P^{*})\). Hence,

$$\begin{aligned} U_i^c(y_i) + U_i^g\left( P'(i)\right) - V_i^0(p') \ge U_i^c(x_i) + U_i^g\left( P^{*}(i)\right) - V_i^0(p) \end{aligned}$$

for all i, with strict inequality for some i. As \(P^*\) is the unique optimal group structure based solely on group preferences, we obtain \(U^g_i(P'(i))\le U^g_i(P^*(i))\) for all i by Fact 1 (i). Moreover, \( U_i^c(x_i) = V_i^0(p)\) holds because of (i). Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} U_i^c(y_i) - V_i^0(p') \ge U_i^c(x_i) - V_i^0(p) = 0 \end{aligned}$$

for all individuals i, with strict inequality for some individual. Now pick \(j\in I\) with \(U_j^c(y_j)> V_j^0(p')\). If for some \(i\in P'(j)\), \(p'y_i< p'\omega _{\{i\}}\) , then local non-satiation implies \(V_i^0(p') > U_i^c(y_i)\), contradicting \(U_i^c(y_i)\ge V_i^0(p')\). Therefore, \(p'y_i\ge p'\omega _{\{i\}}\) for all \(i\in P'(j)\). Since \(\mathbf {y\!}_{_{P'\!(j)}}\in {EB\!}_{_{P'(j)}}(p')\), this implies \(p'y_i = p'\omega _{\{i\}}\) and, consequently, \(U_i^c(y_i)\le V_i^0(p')\) for all \(i\in P'(j)\). Thus a contradiction to \(U_j^c(y_j)> V_j^0(p')\) results. Hence, to the contrary, it cannot be the case that in the CEFE \((p', \mathbf {y}; P')\), real power is higher for some individuals and not lower for any individual than in \((p, \mathbf {x}; P^{*})\). \(\square \)

Proof of Fact 3

step 1: We first determine equilibrium quantities and examine the non-exit conditions in case \(P=\{I\}\). Given the price system \(p=(1,p_2)\), group \(\{1,2,3\}\) solves

$$\begin{aligned}&\max _{\left( x_1^1,x_2^2, x_3^1, x_3^2\right) } \left[ \alpha _1 \left( \ln x_1^1 + \ln v_1\right) + \alpha _2 \left( \ln x_2^2 + \ln v_2\right) \right. \\&\quad \left. + \frac{1}{2}(1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2)\left( \ln x_3^1 + \ln x_3^2 + 2\ln v_3\right) \right] \end{aligned}$$

subject to \(x_1^1+x_3^1+p_2x_2^2+p_2x_3^2=1+p_2\). This yields

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} x_1^1=\alpha _1\cdot (1+p_2), x_2^2=\alpha _2 \cdot (1+p_2)/p_2,\\ x_3^1=(1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2)\cdot (1+p_2)/2, x_3^2=(1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2) \cdot (1+p_2)/(2p_2). \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

The stand-alone demands are:

$$\begin{aligned} x_1^{10}=\dfrac{1}{2}p_2, x_2^{20}=\dfrac{1}{2}, x_3^{10}=\dfrac{1}{2}, x_3^{20}=\dfrac{1}{2p_2}. \end{aligned}$$

The market clearing price is given by \(1+p_2^*=\dfrac{2}{1+\alpha _1-\alpha _2}\).

Then the non-exit condition for the first individual is:

$$\begin{aligned} \ln \left( \alpha _1\left( p_2^*+1\right) \right) + \ln v_1 \ge \ln \left( \frac{1}{2}p_2^* \right) , \end{aligned}$$

which is equivalent to \(\alpha _1 \ge \frac{p_2^*}{2(p_2^*+1)v_1}\) and \(\alpha _1 \ge \frac{1+\alpha _2}{4v_1+ 1}\).

Similarly, for the second individual we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \ln \left( \alpha _2 \frac{p_2^*+1}{p_2^*} \right) + \ln v_2 \ge \ln \frac{1}{2} \end{aligned}$$

or \(\alpha _2 \ge \frac{p_2^*}{(p_2^*+1)2v_2}\) which is equivalent to \(\alpha _2 \ge \frac{1-\alpha _1}{4v_2-1}\).

Finally, the third individual’s non-exit condition amounts to

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{1}{2} \left\{ \ln \frac{1}{2} + \ln \frac{1}{2p_2^*} \right\} \le \frac{1}{2} \ln \left( (1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2)\frac{p_2^*+1}{2} \right) \\&\quad + \frac{1}{2} \ln \left( (1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2)\frac{p_2^*+1}{2p_2^*} \right) +\ln v_3. \end{aligned}$$

It implies \((1-\alpha _1 - \alpha _2)(p_2^*+1) \ge 1/v_3\) or \(1-\alpha _1-\alpha _2 \ge (1+\alpha _1-\alpha _2)/(2v_3)\) or \(\alpha _1 \le \frac{2v_3-1}{2v_3+1}\cdot (1-\alpha _2)\).

step 2: We next examine whether real power of individual 1 can be equal or higher under the group structure \(P = \{\{ 1,2 \}, \, \{3 \}\}\) than under \(P^* = \{ I\}\). That is, we examine whether it is possible to delineate parameter values such that \({\rho _1} \ge \max \{\rho _1^*\}\), where \({\rho _1}=\ln \frac{1}{2} + \ln v_1 + \ln (4 \alpha )\) for \(\alpha \in [\frac{1}{2},1-\frac{1}{2v_2}]\) (from Example 2) and \(\rho _1^*\) is 1’s real power in the above equilibrium. When choosing the maximal \(\alpha = 1-\frac{1}{2v_2}\), the inequality is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \ln \left( \frac{4v_2-2}{2v_2} \right) \ge \max \Biggl \{ \ln \left( \frac{2\alpha _1(1+p_2^*)}{p_2^*} \right) \Biggr \} \end{aligned}$$

which implies

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{4v_2-2}{2v_2} \ge \max \Biggl \{ \frac{4\alpha _1}{1-\alpha _1+\alpha _2}\Biggr \}. \end{aligned}$$

Observe that with \(\alpha _1=\alpha _2=1/4\), all three non-exit conditions are satisfied and individual 1 enjoys real power \(\rho _1^*=\ln v_1>0\) in the corresponding CEFE. Therefore, in order to maximize \(\rho _1^*\), it suffices to solve the following problem:

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{\alpha _1, \alpha _2 \in [0,1]} \left\{ \frac{4\alpha _1}{1-\alpha _1+\alpha _2} \right\} \end{aligned}$$

         s.t.

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _2\ge & {} \frac{1-\alpha _1}{4v_2-1}, \\ \alpha _1\le & {} \frac{2v_3-1}{2v_3+1}\cdot (1-\alpha _2). \end{aligned}$$

It follows that the optimal solution for \(\alpha _2\) is given by \(\alpha _2=\frac{1-\alpha _1}{4v_2-1}\) since \(\frac{\partial \rho _1^*}{\partial \alpha _2}<0, \frac{\partial \rho _1^*}{\partial \alpha _1}>0\) and the right-hand side of the last constraint is monotonically decreasing in \(\alpha _2\). Hence our problem is reduced to

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{\alpha _1 \in [0,1]}\left\{ \frac{(4v_2-1)\alpha _1}{v_2(1-\alpha _1)} \right\} \end{aligned}$$

where the constraint amounts to

$$\begin{aligned} (2v_3+1)\alpha _1 \le (2v_3-1)\cdot \left( 1- \frac{1-\alpha _1}{4v_2-1} \right) \end{aligned}$$

which leads to

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1 \le \frac{(2v_2-1)(2v_3-1)}{2(v_2-v_3+2v_3v_2)}<1. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, maximization of \(\rho _1^*\) is obtained by

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1 = \frac{(2v_2-1)(2v_3-1)}{2(v_2-v_3+2v_3v_2)}. \end{aligned}$$

Now based on the foregoing transformation, the inequality \({\rho _1} \ge \max \{\rho _1^*\}\) leads to

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{4v_2-2}{2v_2} \ge \frac{(4v_2-1)\alpha _1}{v_2(1-\alpha _1)} \end{aligned}$$

which implies \(\alpha _1 \le \frac{2v_2-1}{6v_2-2}\). Hence, \(\widehat{\rho _1}\ge \max \{\rho _1^*\}\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{(2v_2-1)(2v_3-1)}{2(v_2-v_3+2v_2v_3)} \le \frac{2v_2-1}{6v_2-2} \end{aligned}$$

which implies \(4v_3v_2 -4v_2-v_3 \le -1\) or \(4v_2(v_3-1)\le v_3-1\).

Since \(v_3>1\), the latter implies \(4v_2 \le 1\) which contradicts \(v_2\ge 1\) and, therefore, \(\widehat{\rho _1} < \max \{\rho _1^*\}\) has to hold.

Hence, there are no parameter constellations such that the maximal real power of individual 1 in a CEFE with \(P=I\) is strictly smaller than \(\widehat{\rho _1}\). \(\square \)

Notice that in case \(v_3=1\), we are back to Example 2 and \(\widehat{\rho _1} = \max \{\rho _1^*\}\). In fact, in case \(v_3=1\), the foregoing proof shows that \(\widehat{\rho _1} > \max \{\rho _1^*\}\) would yield \(0=4v_2(v_3-1) < v_3-1 =0\) and, thus, \(0<0\); therefore, \(\widehat{\rho _1} \le \max \{\rho _1^*\}\) has to hold.

Proof of Proposition 5

Good \(\ell \) serves as a numéraire so that the price system assumes the form \((p_1, \ldots , p_{\ell -1}, 1)\). We are focusing on interior solutions regarding all commodities, including the numéraire good.Footnote 10 Let us consider then the first-order conditions for maximizing \(\ln S_h\) in group h, subject to h’s budget constraint:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{rcl} \beta _h \displaystyle {\frac{1}{ U_{h1} - U_{h1}\left( x^0_{h1}(p);\{h1\}\right) } \frac{ \partial V_{h1} }{ \partial x^k_{h1} } } - \lambda _h p_k &{} = &{} 0, \; \; \; k=1, \ldots , \ell -1; \\ \beta _h \displaystyle { \frac{1}{ U_{h1} - U_{h1}\left( x^0_{h1}(p); \{h1\}\right) }} - \lambda _h &{} = &{} 0; \\ (1-\beta _h) \displaystyle { \frac{1}{ U_{h2} - U_{h2}\left( x^0_{h2}(p); \{h2\}\right) } \frac{ \partial V_{h2} }{ \partial x^k_{h2} }} - \lambda _h p_k &{} = &{} 0, \; \; \; k=1, \ldots , \ell -1; \\ (1-\beta _h) \displaystyle { \frac{1}{ U_{h2} - U_{h2}\left( x^0_{h2}(p); \{h2\}\right) }} - \lambda _h &{} = &{} 0. \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

Therefore:

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _h= & {} \beta _h \frac{1}{ U_{h1} - U_{h1}\left( x^0_{h1}(p); \{h1\}\right) } = (1-\beta _h) \frac{1}{ U_{h2} - U_{h2}\left( x^0_{h2}(p); \{h2\}\right) }. \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(10)
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ \partial V_{h1} }{ \partial x^k_{h1} }= & {} \frac{ \partial V_{h2} }{ \partial x^k_{h2} } = p_k, \; \; \; k=1, \ldots , \ell -1. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Equation (11) implies that the demand of group h for commodities \(k=1, \ldots , \ell -1\) is independent of the bargaining power \(\beta _h\) and \(1-\beta _h\) of individual h1 and h2, respectively. Since the \(V_{hi}\) are strictly concave and strictly increasing, the budget of the particular group h is exhausted. It follows that h’s total demand for commodity \(\ell \) is independent of \(\beta _h\) as well. Therefore, aggregate demand and, thus, equilibria in commodity markets do not depend on internal bargaining power of groups. As a consequence, changes of bargaining power in group h have no effect on equilibrium prices. This establishes points (i) and (ii).

However, a shift of the power in groups affects the distribution of the numéraire good in group h. Using the notation for the equilibria we have from Eq. (10):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\beta _h}{ \widehat{V}_{h1} + \widehat{x}_{h1}^{\ell } + v_{1} - U_{h1}\left( x^0_{h1}(\widehat{p}); \{h1\}\right) } = \frac{1-\beta _h}{ \widehat{V}_{h2} + \widehat{x}_{h2}^{\ell } + v_{2} - U_{h2}\left( x^0_{h2}(\widehat{p}); \{h2\}\right) }\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(12)

Since \(\widehat{V}_{h1}, v_{1}, U_{h1}(x^0_{h1}(\widehat{p}); \{h1\})\) and \(\widehat{V}_{h2}, v_{2}, U_{h2}(x^0_{h2}(\widehat{p}); \{h2\})\) are independent of \(\beta _h\) and \(\widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h1} + \widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h2}\) does not depend on \(\beta _h\) either, we obtain point (iii):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ \partial \widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h1} }{ \partial \beta _h } > 0, \; \; \frac{ \partial \widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h2} }{ \partial \beta _h } < 0 \end{aligned}$$

Furthermore, Eq. (12) is tantamount to (iv).

If groups are completely homogeneous with respect to \(U_{hi}\) and \(w_h\), a group equilibrium does not involve any positive net trades, again using the fact that differences in \(\beta _h\) have no effect on aggregate excess demand. Therefore, \(\widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h1} + \widehat{x}^{\ell }_{h2} = \omega ^{\ell }_{h}\) and via Eq. (12) we obtain (v). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gersbach, H., Haller, H. Power at general equilibrium. Soc Choice Welf 50, 425–455 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1091-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1091-3

Navigation